At the time this article was published Paul
Benoit worked for the federal government in Ottawa. He is the author of several
articles on Canadian history and politics.
John George Bourinot was Clerk of the House
of Commons from 1880 until his death in 1902. Although best known for his book
on parliamentary procedure, Bourinot devoted his leisure time to the study of
the principles of government. He wrote voluminously on the subject and many of
his books became standard works in Great Britain and the colonies. Bourinot
frequently lectured at universities in the United States and has some claim to
being considered the first political scientist in Canada.1
In Bourinot's eyes, Confederation established
a Dominion of which one could truly be proud but its complexity required of its
citizens considerable knowledge and understanding. He was fond of saying that
with Confederation Canada became "heir of all the ages" inheriting
both the fruits of British experience with parliamentary government and
American experience with federal government. Directly or indirectly, all his
writings turn on Confederation which he saw as that union of the best of two
worlds.
Considering how much has been written about
Confederation in the past twenty years, it is strange that scarcely any
attention has been paid to Bourinot.2 His views merit consideration not only
because he was one of Canada's first political scientist but he was also an
important official of the Canadian Parliament during its formative years and
finally because he was a Maritimer. If one has difficulty discerning a
specifically Maritime point of view in recent constitutional debate, a voice
from the past would seem better than none.
The Nature of Confederation
Describing the first century and a half of
European settlement in North America, Bourinot emphasized its past politics:
"In the days of the French régime... a system of centralization was
established by Louis Quatorze, who so pitilessly during his reign enforced
'that dependence which', as Saint Simon tells us, 'reduced all to subjection',
everything like local freedom was stifled, and the most insignificant matters
of local concern were kept under the direct control of the council and especially
of the intendant at Quebec."3 He called the history of Canada as a French
colony, a record of autocratic government giving no opportunity to the
expansion of energy and intellect.
Bourinot then contrasted the highly
centralized government of New France with the highly decentralized government
of New England: "It is easy to understand that there could be no such
things as free government or representative institutions in Canada, like those
enjoyed from the very commencement of their history by the old English colonies
which were founded almost contemporaneously with the settlement of Acadia and
Canada."4 Clearly the meetings of a Boston town hall were more attractive
to Bourinot than the intrigues of a Bourbon court. The English speaking
colonies, by providing scope for local civil liberty, represented for Bourinot
a more advanced stage of constitutional development.
But subsequently, and rather paradoxically,
those colonies which remained faithful to the Crown came to acquire a more
progressive form of government than those which had rebelled. Bourinot
explained how:
In the United States when the constitution
was formed parliamentary government, as it is now understood in England and her
self governing dependencies, was not understood in its complete significance.
The framers of the American constitution saw only two prominent powers, the
king and parliament, and their object was to impose a system of checks and
balances which would restrain the authority of each and prevent any one
dominating in the nation.5
In England a way was found to eliminate
friction between the two branches of government by making the ministers of the
Crown responsible to Parliament. When England moved from a state of opposition
between the executive and the legislative to one of co-operation, a more
sophisticated form of government emerged one that the remaining British
colonies in North America acquired beginning in 1848.
The 1850s and early 1860s are very important
in Bourinot's mind because they testify to the successful operation in the New
World of "a constitution similar in principle to that of the United
Kingdom." They illustrate the ability of the separate colonies to govern
themselves along the lines of the most progressive form of government evolved
by man.
Given the emphasis on local self-government
which we have already detected in his writings, it should not surprise us that
Bourinot viewed Confederation as essentially a compact. To him, the provinces'
authority to govern was not dependent on the fate of the new Dominion: "If
the dominion should cease tomorrow to exercise its constitutional powers, the
province would still remain for its existed before the union and its local
organization could very soon be extended to embrace those powers which now
belong to the central authority."6 Bourinot then outlined his account of
Confederation.
The weight of authority now clearly rests
with those who have always contended that in entering into the federal compact
the provinces never intended to renounce their distinct and separate existence
as provinces, when they became part of the Confederation. This separate
existence was expressly reserved for all that concerns their internal
government; and in forming themselves into a federal association under
political and legislative aspects they formed a central government for
inter-provincial objects only. Far from the federal authority having created
the provincial powers, it is from these provincial powers that there has arisen
the federal government to which the provinces ceded a portion of their rights,
property and revenues.7
Bourinot's account of Confederation as a
compact naturally led him to criticize some features of the British North
America Act. Three in particular he singled out: the constitution of the upper
house; the existence of the power of disallowance; and the financial dependence
of the provinces to a large extent on the Dominion exchequer.
Bourinot's proposal that the Senate be
reformed so as to make it more representative of provincial interests has
become commonplace in nearly all assessments of the Canadian constitution. The
federal cabinet's power to nominate the chief magistrates of the provinces is,
for Bourinot, another example of "a tendency to give the ministry too
superior a control."8
The federal power of disallowance, though
exercised only rarely, was objectionable for two reasons. First, it called on
politicians to assume the role of judges: "An executive power which can be
thus questioned in the political arena seems obviously fraught was perilous
consequences. If all questions of the constitutionality of a provincial act
could be decided only in the courts, parliament would be saved the discussion
of matters which, once mixed up with political and religious issues, must
necessarily be replete with danger in a country like Canacia."9 The second
objection was that "the central power might in a moment of passion or
arrogance use its authority to check or thwart the government made subordinate
to it in this particular."10 As long as the federal government had the
right to disallow provincial legislation there was no area that the provinces
could consider safe from jurisdictional encroachment.
With regard to the financial dependence of
the provinces, Bourinot explained that:
As a large portion of their provincial
revenues – in certain cases the largest portion – is not derived from local
sources, there has not been always, it is believed, that effort for economical
expenditure that would probably have been made if all the funds were raised
from local sources, and from direct taxation as in the United States... Each
province should be, as far as possible, in a position of local independence,
and tree from suspicion of political pressure on the central government at
critical times.11
Bourinot's remarks have since been elaborated
into the argument against conditional and unconditional grants (and other forms
of co-operative or administrative federalism) which tend to blur the lines of
accountability and make it difficult to hold any particular minister or
official responsible.
The Legislative versus the Judicial
The compact theory of Confederation as
articulated by Bourinot has been out of fashion among English Canadian
politicians and publicists since the 1930s. Yet in being one of the first to
make a strong case for the provinces, Bourinot emerges as the godfather of a
host of current constitutional proposals. For example his account of
Confederation anticipated recent constitutional changes which have enhanced the
role of the judiciary.
In theory, the Canadian constitution is an
even mixture of British experience with an unwritten constitution and American
experience with a written one. But in practice, the exigencies of public
affairs lead one to have recourse to the wisdom stored in one or the other. In
the crunch of a constitutional conflict to whom does one turn as the final
arbiter? To a group of politicians acting as a team of ministers responsible to
Parliament or to a group of lawyers acting as a body of individual judges not
responsible to anyone? Bourinot explained how federalism by its very nature
tipped the balance in the judged favour:
Any federal system like that of Canada must,
in a great measure, gather its real strength from the decisions of the courts
which are called upon, from time to time, to adjudicate on the many questions
that arise with respect to the rights and powers of the several provinces which
have entered into what may be considered a solemn treaty, to which the Imperial
Parliament, as the supreme legislative authority of the Empire, has given its authoritative
legal sanction. Accordingly, the security of the federal union largely rests on
the legal acumen and independence of the courts.12
Furthermore, it is clear that Bourinot
approved of the supremacy of the judiciary:
Not only the life and prosperity of the
people, but the satisfactory working of the whole system of federal government
rests more or less on the discretion and integrity of the judges. Canadians are
satisfied that the peace and security of the whole Dominion do not more depend
on the ability and patriotism of statesmen in the legislative halls than on
that principle of the constitution which places the judiciary in an exalted
position among all the other departments of government and makes law as far as
possible the arbiter of their constitutional conflicts.13
But in positing a court of law above and
independent of the political life of a country, is one not making it very
difficult for any central executive authority to respond or to adjust to any
collective purpose that may gradually be evolving in the country? It is no
accident that the new Canada Act which has made the Supreme Court the guardian
of a new constitution and an entrenched bill of rights has coincided with
demands by certain provincial governments for greater power, and with a general
desire on the part of many Canadians to see the power of the federal government
reduced.
Self-Determination of Provinces
Bourinot's account of Confederation also
anticipated the provinces' claims to self-determination. He believed the provinces
never intended to renounce their separate existence; that the federal
government was the creature of the provinces, not vice versa. Thus if Canada
should come to an end, the provinces, having pre-existed would remain to take
over its powers. Strengthening a Canadian province's claim to
self-determination are two compelling notions: the notion of local civil
liberty and the notion of popular sovereignty.
In North America, the European settlement of
distinct and separate colonies provided to a large extent the basis for the
local communities of today. It also provided our model of civil liberty: the
sight of a small group of citizens assembling, deliberating, passing
resolutions, and carrying them into effect. It seems appropriate that his most
widely consulted work, the one for which he is most remembered is his Rules of
Order. Furthermore for Bourinot the government's authority i.e., its right to
command and be obeyed stems not from the person of the Monarch, but from the
collective will of the people. It is the latter which renders legitimate all
enactments of public policy. In Bourinot's eyes, it was not Queen Victoria's
assent (or that of her representative) which lent authority to the
constitutional arrangements being worked out in the North America colonies; it
was rather the consent of the people inhabiting them. Thus, for example,
Bourinot interprets the governor general's right to dissolve Parliament the
royal prerogative par excellence as essentially a means for the people to
assert their sovereignty: "A Governor, acting always under the advice of
responsible ministers, may, at any time, generally speaking, grant an appeal to
the people to test their opinion on vital public questions and bring the
Legislature into accord with the public mind. In short, the fundamental
principle of popular sovereignty lies at the very basis of the Canadian
system."14
In theory, there is no reason why the notion
of popular sovereignty cannot be invoked to support the expansion of an empire,
but in practice it has usually been employed to reinforce the claims of a
community wishing to break free. Today, for example, there is hardly a
politician in Canada who would maintain that the Quebec referendum was devoid
of any moral authority, that its verdict stands for nothing more than a crude
measurement of public opinion. A belief that authority flows upward, out of a
community's consent, leads inevitably to a desire and a willingness on the part
of that community to assert its identity. When a belief in popular sovereignty is
coupled with a belief in local civil liberty, they produce, in the Canadian
context, the right of the provinces to self-determination, a powerful
dissolvent of national unity.
Politics and Ethics
Bourinot's account of Confederation is not,
however, perfectly clear-cut. There are ambiguities in his thought which will
become apparent if we examine an article he wrote on whether municipal
officials should be appointed or elected.15
Bourinot begins by explaining to his readers
how "the people legislate and govern through their representative
assemblies."16 For Bourinot, not only does the authority to make laws come
from the people; it is even exercised by the people representatives being but
the people's efficient agents. Now while it is doubtful that such a view is, as
Bourinot claims, "in accordance with the wise principles of English
government", it is in accordance with Bourinot's belief in popular
sovereignty Having claimed so much for the people, Bourinot goes on to object
to the election of officials. Any experimenting with the elective system, he
says, "would be literally the thin edge of a wedge which would gradually
and surely split up the durable foundation on which government rests."17
Elsewhere, and in accordance with his belief
in the primacy of local self government, he describes municipal government as
"those local institutions on which must always rest, in a great measure,
the whole fabric of popular liberty"18 and as the very basis of Canada's
parliamentary institutions".19 Still he goes on to question the wisdom of
electing aldermen: It is the elective principle that is now in question, when
applied to men whose duties are those of managers of a corporation. Indeed
there are many influential and thinking men in Canadian cities – in Toronto especially
who express the opinion that a small permanent commission appointed by the
government would best manage civic affairs."20 We are left to wonder: are
Canada's cities to be viewed as meeting grounds where people can learn to
govern themselves and prepare themselves to take part in the larger councils of
the world? Or, are they simply corporations, the management of which should be
left to a small permanent commission appointed by the provincial cabinet?
The same ambiguity is to be found in
Bourinot's estimation of referendums and plebiscites. He has sympathy for
Swiss-style referendums but contempt for French-style plebiscites. It is
difficult to see how the two can be held so very far apart. The ambiguity is
due to the fact that while his intellectual convictions led him in one
direction, his moral concerns led him in another For Bourinot laxity of morals
in society must tend to lower the political conditions of a country. It was on
the basis of a substantive moral consideration that Bourinot objected to the
extension of the principle of election: "Can anyone argue that the body of
the voting public who elect can be made responsible for the result? The
legislature in the first place, and the people at a final stage, can censure a
government, or turn it out of office, since ministers are directly responsible
for every act of administration. But who will check the people?"21 It was
impossible to hold the voter morally responsible for his action, and therein
lay the danger of extending the principle of election. The experience of the
United States, where the principle of election was widely extended, showed:
that the party machine, as managed by the
boss, is destructive of public morality; that it is the elective and the
"spoils" system by which a horde of public officials obtain office
that gives vitality to the machine and its creatures, and is weakening the
foundations of republican or democratic institutions; that rings and bosses
will exist and thrive as long as the great majority of public officers, including
judges, are elected or appointed on political lines.22
Writing in 1897, Bourinot cited the case of
the American election just past: In the remarkable presidential election of
November last in the United States we saw the perilous tendencies of demagoguism
in a country of universal franchise, elective officials and pure democracy. The
spirit of the Demos is dangerous in the extreme when it is not surrounded by
the checks and guards which restrain its power and lead it in the direction of
sound, stable and strong government."23 Clearly the practices which
developed as a result of "universal franchise, elective officials and pure
democracy" were morally objectionable to Bourinot. But the substantive
concern he evinced is in conflict with his formal conviction that people should
govern themselves. How else can the members of a local community determine
their own political destiny if not by going frequently to the polls, casting
their vote in one direction or another, and abiding by the opinion of the majority?
There are a number of other instances of
moral concern to be found throughout his writings. The levelling tendency, the
laxity of marriage ties, the sensationalism of newspapers: these and other U.S.
mores repelled Bourinot, who was anxious that such should not become the case
in Canada. Indeed, Bourinot's concern with the moral dimension of human
behaviour led him to view certain social practices as "public
wrongs;" rather than "civil rights".
The correcting of public wrongs is a task
incumbent solely upon the central government. While it is difficult to see how
far Bourinot would want to extend the concept of public wrong, and thereby the
scope for federal intervention, it is clear that we have, in this concept, a
lever capable of drastically altering the balance of federal-provincial power.
What would the consequences be today of viewing practices such as pollution,
energy waste, certain forms of advertising and pornography as public wrongs.
Bourinot once defined federalism as "a
system which rests on the basis of local self government and a central
authority".24 We sense in this definition the same ambiguity: the two
terms 1ocal selfgovernment" and "central authority" do not quite
hang together. Where in the final analysis, does the authority to govern come
from? Is it an expression of the collective will of the people as manifest, for
example, in the results of a provincial referendum held to decide whether or
not that province should join (or separate from) a federal union; or is
authority an expression of the individual judgement of the government as
manifest, for example, in the Crown's decision that the exercise of a
particular civil right has gone beyond the bounds of reason and has become a
public wrong? Once one has granted the principle of popular sovereignty, once
one allows that the task of the legislature is to bring public questions into
accord with the public mind, then what central authority is there left 1o
restrain the spirit of Demos and lead it in the direction of sound, stable and strong
government"?
Conclusion
Bourinot showed considerable respect for the
mosaic of distinct communities that settled North America. He developed his
liberal convictions into a strong argument for viewing Confederation as a
compact between the, representative of some of those communities, but
ethically, Bourinot proved to be a conservative who clung to the belief that
morals were still the legitimate concern of politicians; and that consequently
there was a need for a strong central authority capable of assuring the peace,
order and good government of the country as a whole. His writings reveal the
difficulty of keeping aligned one's, intellectual convictions about the best
form of government, and one's moral concerns about man's behaviour in society. The
difficulty is part of the predicament of human nature and it is really in this
sense (never intended by Sir John) that Canada is "the heir of all the
ages".
Notes
1. As an example of the pioneering work
Bourinot did in this field, see his "The Study of Political Science in
Canadian Universities", Transactions of the Royal Society of Canada,
Vol. VII (1889), sec. Ii, pp. 3-16.
2. The only scholarly article on Bourinot,
Carl Berger's "Race and Liberty: The Historical Ideas of Sir John George
Bourinot", C.H.A. Annual Report (1965) pp. 87-104 – deals mainly
with his imperialism and his racism. But these two aspects of his thoughts are,
in my opinion, peripheral and reflect but common assumptions of his age, though
perhaps they account for the neglect he had been subject to in ours.
3. Bourinot, Federal Government, p.
149.
4. Ibid., p. 10.
5. J.G. Bourinot, "Canada and the
United States: A Study in Comparative Politics" Annals of the American
Academy of Political and Social Science (July 1890), p. 13.
6. Bourinot, Federal Government, op.
cit. P. 76.
7. Ibid., p. 124.
8. John G. Bourinot, " Canadian Studies
in Comparative Politics", Transactions of the Royal Society of Canada,
Vol. XI (1893), sec. Ii. P. 92ff.
9. Bourinot, Federal Government, op.
cit. P. 64.
10. Ibid., p. 62.
11. Ibid., pp. 74-75.
12. J.G. Bourinot, "English Principles
of Canadian Government", Canadian Magazine, Vol. IX (June 1897) p.
96.
13. Bourinot, Canada Under British Rule,
p. 281.
14. Bourinot, "English
Principles", op. cit. p. 98.
15. J.G. Bourinot, "Elected or
Appointed Officials? A Canadian Question", Annals of the American
Academy of Political and Social Science (March 1895).
16. Ibid., p. 8.
17. Ibid., p. 30.
18. J.G. Bourinot, "Local Government in
Canada", Transactions of the Royal Society of Canada, Vol. IV
(1886), sec, ii. P. 43.
19. J.G. Bourinot, Parliamentary
Procedure and Practice in the Dominion of Canada, Shannon, 1971, p. 32.
20. Bourinot, "Elected or Appointed
Officials?", op. cit. p. 22.
21. Ibid., p. 23.
22. Ibid., p. 24.
23. Bourinot, "English
Principles", op. cit. p. 101.
24. Bourinot, "The Study of Political
Science" (1889) op. cit. p. 10.