At the time this article was
written Pierre Coulombe was a Professor of Political Science at the University
of Western Ontario
An analysis of the latest constitutional
plan brings us back, once again, to a crossroads. Basically, we have been there
since 1982. What the failure of the Charlottetown Accord confirms is that
English Canada appears to be pursuing national affirmation, relying on a
discourse based on the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms that
leaves little room for competing forms of nationalism, whether native or
French-Canadian. This discourse makes it improbable that a constitutional
agreement will become a reality.
One recalls how the rejection of
the Meech Lake Accord had sounded the death knell of executive federalism. What
formerly seemed justified in the name of maintaining the fragile balance
between the two national communities would from then on be the subject of
condemnation and contempt: condemnation because, it was said, executive
federalism served provincial interests more than "national" ones; and
contempt because it placed greater value on the supposedly elitist discourse of
the negotiators than on the voice of so-called ordinary Canadians. Since blame
was assigned to executive federalism, it was most important not to see the
rejection of Meech as a rejection of Quebec's claims. The next round would be
more sound: it would encompass the claims from the West and the native peoples
and would be the fruit of public participation. Above all, however, it would
reflect English Canada's self-image, as seen through the prism of the Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms.
In due course the Charlottetown
Accord was negotiated. It, too, would fail, despite unprecedented participation
by Canadians in developing it. There is no point in recalling here the sad
details of that failure. This time, the new scapegoat would be the vote of
non-confidence in the Mulroney government and, for good measure, a rejection of
the entire political class. It was as if many Canadians were shouting the
"No" they wished they had said during the Meech round. Behind the
scenes, however, the Charlottetown Accord was arraigned by the proponents of
Canada's civic identity, strong in the Charter.
The magnitude of this latest
failure is underestimated. It is indeed a monumental failure, not just a chance
accident on the road toward the inevitable compromise. It expresses what more
than one observer has noted, a powerful discourse on the Canadian Charter of
Rights and Freedoms that endows with new legitimacy the traditional refusal
to recognize the two national communities within the federation.1 In
a way, it is the latest attack on Canadian duality, enlivened this time by a
deficient liberal morality.
Firstly, this Charter-based
political culture of English-speaking Canada evokes a national civic identity
that transcends federalism and the communities that divide it.2 From
this perspective, the Charlottetown Accord was problematic because it was to
entrench the fact that some Canadians belong to a community of identity other
than the Canadian "nation". The unity of the Canadian people--or at
least the search for a form of unity--would have been undermined in advance by
recognition of values conferring different constitutional statuses on persons
of different origins or from different regions. By referring to Quebec as a
distinct political community, the Charlottetown Accord--like the Meech Lake
Accord--would have challenged the plan for equality among citizens, the
keystone of this new national identity.
Secondly, some supporters of the
"No" side were able to brandish the Charter to invoke the risks to
human rights the Accord would have brought with it. Pierre Trudeau's categorical
remarks naturally come to mind. Although his extreme opinions were not
universally shared, a number of persons still considered that the Accord
threatened individual rights. Three points were most often raised.3
Firstly, the Canada clause seemed to create a hierarchy of rights that, sooner
or later, would have eroded the system of interpreting the rights and freedoms
contained in the Charter. Next, the distinct society clause might well have
limited, in Quebec, the protections provided by the Charter. Lastly, the
Charter was prevented from addressing too many aspects of the exercise of
self-government by native people.
It is obvious that such a discourse
is in conflict with the claims to nationhood by French Canada in general and
Quebec in particular--not that individual rights are less respected there than
elsewhere.4 After all, both the Quebec courts and the Supreme Court
of Canada struck down the sections of Bill 101 making French the sole language
of signage. Furthermore, there is a tendency to forget that not only the Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms, but the Quebec Charter of Human Rights and
Freedoms itself, supported the merchants' cause. The issue of conflict between
individual rights and collective language rights, then, has its source in
Quebec itself. The Canadian Charter is problematic more because the idea of a
Canadian people with an identity based on the Charter is hardly compatible with
the concept of Canadian duality. The Charter culture makes it possible to unite
citizens under the auspices of a system of rights guaranteeing equal status
within the nation regardless of age, sex, language, ethnic origin or other
factors. It is, therefore, a dynamic that cuts through French Canada as a
national community by appealing to pan-Canadian identities and thus
circumventing the relationship between individual citizens and duality.
The problem of the Charter is
different for the native people. For them, it is more a tension between liberal
and community values, a tension that took on its full meaning during the debate
on equality between the sexes and self-government. The liberal equation is
simple: native people have the right to have the conditions of their own
identity preserved, as long as the liberal values of free choice and individual
atonomy are given priority over community traditions. However, vulnerable
minority communities hesitate to pledge allegiance to a liberal discourse that
too often masks cultural imperialism. Indeed, it is easy for members of a
dominant group, who know that market forces work to their advantage, to invoke
liberal morality. Of course, the misuse of individual rights does not mean we
should do away with them. That is not the point. The challenge lies in the
search for a balance between the conditions of political citizenship--as
imposed by the Charter--and the conditions of belonging to a community.
In summary, three major forces are
in opposition: the new political culture of Canada outside Quebec, based on the
Charter; the will of French Canada to escape being reduced to folklore in the
restructuring movement of the Canadian dynamic; and native resistance to an
inflexible liberal discourse.
A number of difficulties loom.
Logically, it is hard to imagine how the various players could come to the
constitutional table with fewer claims than they had previously. It is unlikely
that the Western provinces will accept less than a genuine triple-E Senate. It
is also improbable that Quebec will be satisfied with entrenchment of the
status quo regarding the distribution of legislative powers, or that
asymmetrical federalism will replace the doctrine of equality among the
provinces. Where native issues are concerned, the Canadian public can be
expected to be more vigilant and even more mistrustful about what implementing self-government
means in concrete terms. To these factors are added public participation, which
will only increase, and English Canada's growing fascination with a constituent
assembly--a process that may well drown Quebec's claims once again in the myriad
of interests invoking the Charter, not to mention the strong likelihood that in
that process French-Canadian minorities would find themselves relegated to the
background.
A possible response to these
concerns is that in politics compromise is always possible. It is clearly felt
that the compromise approach of the Charlottetown Accord will have to be set
aside. When agreement is seen as compromise with one's conscience,5
positions can be expected to harden.
Beyond political strategies,
however, one point must be acknowledged concerning French Canada's position in
the Canadian whole. The Constitution Act, 1982 and the resulting
political culture make the status quo increasingly unacceptable. The issue is
no longer knowing how Quebec could gain advantage by using constructive
ambivalence in a federalism that is manageable, at least in practice. That
federalism, which had long kept alive the French-Canadian dream of full
duality, has been seriously damaged since 1982.6 Since that time, a
system of rights and a concept of citizenship, bolstered by a Charter as a
common measure of both, has been created and has resulted in a clash of
national affirmations.
Does this new system not protect
the minority French-speaking communities? Certainly, constitutional entrenchment
of bilingual federal institutions and the right to education in French
constitutes undeniable progress. Paradoxically, the discourse on the Charter
itself could, in the long run, call such rights into question. Are they not,
after all, collective rights, that is, rights that favour certain individuals
depending on whether they belong to a specific language group? While there is
no need to exaggerate the danger, the new discourse on redefining Canadian
citizenship and the role of this discourse in challenging duality must
nonetheless be understood.
What does the future hold? Certain
separatist rhetoric will undoubtedly try to convince Quebecers of the virtues
of independence, which ignores the problem of the minorities--both
English-speaking in Quebec and French-Canadians elsewhere and which fails to
explain the very real risks of independence: a heavier tax burden, complete
submission to a foreign monetary policy, renegotiation of the Free Trade
Agreement and land claims. Not that secession has no charms: the image of an
independent Quebec is crystal clear, purged of a federal structure that cannot
be renewed without becoming more cumbersome. No longer would citizens'
attachment to this fully sovereign political community be mixed; divided
loyalty and scattered identity would thus be things of the past. Having one's
country is no small thing. (The same is also true for Canada, which, once
liberated from competing Quebec nationalism, could pursue its own nationalism
with one less obstacle.) This plan, then, is a sound asset in the romantic
imagination, but is still too often silent about improvements in day-to-day
life.
One can also imagine a renewed
federalism that would fit French Canada and gain the confidence of a majority
of Quebecers as well as the support of the minority French-speaking
communities. Such a form of federalism would fall somewhere between the Meech
Lake Accord and the "beau risque" of 1985. It would be based on a
recognition of duality across Canada and on Quebec's unique place in the federation.
Undiluted recognition of French Canada as a nation and Quebec as a distinct
society would thus have to be obtained. The language issue would also have to
be cleared up in order to guarantee the integrity of Quebec's Charter of the
French Language and meet the needs of the minority language communities as
well. (In this regard, however, the Brown's decision had provided a perfectly
reasonable compromise.) These aspects would be accompanied by commitment by the
governments--including the Quebec government--to fostering minority
French-speaking communities in all parts of Canada. Any reform to the central
institutions would have to be approved by seven provinces, necessarily
including Quebec, and representing 50 per cent of the population. Federal spending
power in areas of provincial jurisdiction would be delineated, allowing for the
right to opt out with full financial compensation. Where the distribution of
powers is concerned, most Quebecers would probably want their government to
have more control over labour market training, regional development and
immigration, as well as increased power in the telecommunications sector and
within the international French-speaking community. Quebec could take part in
appointing Supreme Court justices, three of whom would be from Quebec, and
could even have the power to appoint Quebec superior court judges. Lastly--and
not least--in Quebec this constitutional reform should replace the Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms almost in its entirety with the Quebec Charter
of Human Rights and Freedoms, and the Quebec Court of Appeal would become the
court of last resort.
Clear, undiluted entrenchment of
such reforms would give French Canada control of its destiny as a nation. The
catch is that, in the rest of Canada, support for such a plan cannot be
obtained except through acceptance of asymmetrical federalism. There is every
reason to believe that the simplistic doctrine of equality among the provinces
and among citizens would still be an obstacle. Furthermore, it is hard to
imagine how English Canada would consent to Quebec's no longer being subject to
the Charter, since the Charter is the symbol and the supreme instrument of the
pan-Canadian civic identity. In summary, resistance to the idea of a genuine
special status for Quebec as the home of the French-Canadian nation seems more
rooted than ever in the new political culture.
A break with the Constitution
Act, 1982, then, may seem necessary from the outset. That Act pulled Quebec
into a dynamic that hardly meets its needs, not so much because of its content
as because of the concept of equality connected with it.
As Christian Dufour lucidly
demonstrates, the Charter is the basic element of a new English Canadian
nationalism that is resistant to any recognition of Quebec's being different
that is not expressed in terms of folklore.7 That is why he proposes
a break after having obtained popular support with the post-1982 Canadian
federation. Elsewhere, Guy Laforest argues that according to Locke's theory of
consent such a break would be legitimate.8 Indeed, the Constitution
Act, 1982 changed Canada's social contract without the consent of Quebec's
elected representatives while simultaneously diminishing the powers of the
National Assembly. As René Lévesque wrote to his federal counterpart, if the
representatives of Lower Canada had realized in 1865 that agreeing to the
federal plan would eventually have deprived them of all protection against
constitutional changes imposed by others, they would certainly never have given
that agreement.9 Since the Constitution Act, 1982 is no less
illegitimate ten years later, a unilateral declaration of sovereignty would
appear entirely justified.
That declaration of sovereignty
could therefore be, paradoxically, the only means for Quebec to affirm its
identity as a distinct society in renegotiating the federal contract. It
remains to be seen whether that declaration would create uncontrollable
momentum toward independence. Whether or not that occurred, one can see from
here the resulting legal tangle, not to mention the reaction of the rest of
Canada.
From the perspective of future
constitutional reform, French Canada must overcome two obstacles to its
development. The first, which has been the main subject of this article, is the
Charter culture, which may well further weaken the concept of Canadian duality.
The solution offered in the Meech Lake Accord and to some extent in the
Charlottetown Accord was to circumscribe that political culture using
protective mechanisms such as the linguistic duality and distinct society
clauses, the double Senate majority, and guaranteed representation in the House
of Commons. That did not work. For the moment, it is illusory to think of
starting up negotiations again on the same basis.
The second obstacle is the
manipulation of concepts so as to mask the issue of French Canada behind the
problem of Quebec. During the past thirty years, the issue of the French
Canadian nation has been evaded, to the point where that expression has become
archaic. However, any constitutional solution must take into account this
reality, both in Quebec and in the rest of Canada, if it wishes to manage
latent conflicts in a sound manner. That acknowledgment means that the future
of the French-speaking minorities outside Quebec must regain its rightful place
on the list of Quebec's constitutional priorities. It also means that Quebec's
nationalist discourse must become clear about its raison d'être. Agreement
among Quebec's minority communities and its French-Canadian majority depends on
this transparency. Venturing to predict the future, I would say that the issue
of the minorities both inside and outside Quebec will be the thorniest of
constitutional problems to come.
Notes
1. On the role of the Charter in
this new political culture, see Alan Cairns, "Citizenship and the New
Constitutional Order", in this journal, Vol. 15, No.3 (fall 1992); Louis
M. Imbeau and Guy Laforest, "Quebec's Distinct Society and the Sense of
Nationhood in Canada", Quebec Studies, No. 13 (1991-92); Kenneth McRoberts,
"Separate Agendas: English Canada and Quebec", Quebec Studies,
No. 13 (1991-92).
2. The following passage is an
example of this evocation: "The vote on the Charlottetown accord should
not be seen as a rejection of French Canada or the country's indigenous
peoples. …On Monday, Canadians said No to this vision of Canada… Canada is not
a community of communities. Canada is not two solitudes, nor 10, nor 100.
Canada is a nation of 27 million individuals." Tami Pailin Nolan,
"Voting No has Brought us Together", Hamilton Spectator,
October 28, 1992.
3. See "Legal Analysis of
Draft Legal Text", distributed by a group of experts headed by Lorraine
Eisenstat Weinrib, October 21, 1992.
4. See Paul Sniderman et al,
"Political Culture and the Problem of Double Standards: Mass and Elite
Attitudes Toward Language Rights in the Canadian Charter of Rights and
Freedoms", Canadian Journal of Political Science, Vol. 22
(1989), pp. 259-284. See also R. Johnson and A. Blais, "Meech Lake and
Mass Politics", Canadian Public Policy, Vol. 14 (special
supplement), pp 25-42.
5. Examples of this perception
include the editorials by Lise Bissonnette in Le Devoir during the
referendum campaign.
6. In "Quebec's Distinct
Society and the Sense of Nationhood in Canada", Louis Imbeau and Guy
Laforest describe this issue well from the perspective of André Laurendeau's
heritage.
7. La rupture tranquille,
Les Éditions du Boréal, 1992, p. 72.
8. "Protéger et promouvoir une
société distincte au Québec", a paper presented to the Commission on the
Political and Constitutional Future of Quebec (working paper No. 4 - views of
experts), Bibliothèque nationale du Québec, January 17, 1991, pp. 526-528.
9. "De Premier ministre à
Premier ministre. Où nous en sommes, ici au Québec", René Lévesque:
Textes et entrevues 1960-1987, Les Presses de l'Université du Québec, 1991.
pp. 337-338.