At the time this article was published
Philip Norton was Reader in Politics at Hull University in Great Britain. This
is a revised version of his submission to the Special Committee on Reform of
the House of Commons in May 1985.
The belief that a government defeat
necessarily entails resignation or a dissolution has influenced significantly
parliamentary behaviour. It has served to reinforce party cohesion in the
division lobbies. Government backbenchers who disagree with a particular
government policy but who have nonetheless voted for it have on occasion
justified their voting behaviour on the grounds that they "do not wish to
see the other side in office". A number of Conservative backbenchers were
still proffering this explanation in the early 1970s, even after a number of government
defeats, none of which had propelled the government into resigning or
requesting a dissolution. It is, then, clearly a largely ingrained and
powerfully held perception of the government's required response, one which a
number of observers may have been inclined to elevate to the status of a
convention.
It is, however, a perception which rests
upon no continuous basis of practice or upon any authoritative original source
and one which is belied by the experience of both the nineteenth and twentieth
centuries. In the twentieth century alone, the British Government has suffered
more than one hundred defeats in the division lobbies in the House of Commons.
In response to only three of these defeats (two in 1924, one in 1979) did the
government resign or request a dissolution. Indeed, on most of the remaining
occasions, the question of confidence was not seriously considered to have been
raised. When the governments of the l970s suffered a spate of defeats in the
division lobbies (sixty-five in the seven-year period between April 1972 and
April 1979) a number of commentators were of the opinion that: there had been a
change in constitutional practice. They claimed the government of the day was
deviating from past practice in continuing in office, accepting most of the
defeats imposed upon it, and declining to resign or request a dissolution
unless defeated on an express vote of confidence. In fact, clear precedents can
be found for the government's response to each defeat. Far from there being a
deviation from past practice, there was a clear continuation of it.
What, then, is the constitutional position
of the government in the event of a defeat in the division lobbies of the House
of Commons? An analysis of the defeats of the past century suggests that there
are essentially three types of defeat, each of which invites a different
response from government.1
Defeats on Votes of Confidence
A government defeated on a vote of
confidence is expected to resign or seek a dissolution of Parliament. The
precedent was established in 1841 and has been maintained since. What, though,
constitutes a vote of confidence? Three distinct types of vote fall within this
rubric:
(1) Explicitly worded votes of confidence.
These state in express terms that the House has or has not confidence in Her
Majesty's Government. The carrying of a motion of no confidence against the
Government is the strongest and least ambiguous of votes involving the question
of confidence. The passage of such a motion puts it beyond doubt that the government
has lost the confidence of the House there are no other issues to cloud the
picture and that a visit by the Prime Minister to Buckingham Palace is
required, there to request a dissolution of Parliament or to tender the
resignation of the Government.
(2) Motions made votes of confidence by the
declaration of the government. The government, usually at the instigation of
the Prime Minister, may declare that if defeated on a particular motion before
the House, even though not an explicitly-worded one of confidence, it will
resign or seek a dissolution. It may do so because the issue in question is so
central to its policy that there would be little point in continuing in office
if defeated upon it; or it may do so simply as a political expedient in order to
maximise its voting support. It may even do so, in the face of likely defeat,
because it has lost the political will to continue. Though defeats in such
instances are not quite as straightforward as those taking place on explicit
votes of confidence the picture is complicated by the issue which ostensibly is
covered by the motion the position of the government remains the same. Having
lost on a motion which by government declaration is one of confidence, the
Prime Minister must make the trip to the Palace.
(3) Implicit votes of confidence.
Traditionally, certain matters have been deemed to involve confidence, even
though not declared to do so by the prior statement of government. Falling
within this category primarily is the granting of Supply. Failure to grant
Supply is regarded as the established means by which the House can demonstrate
its lack of confidence in the ministry. However, it is a category of vote which
has largely fallen into desuetude. Given the number of divisions which occur
annually on items of Supply, and the fact that the Second Reading debates on
Consolidated Fund Bills ceased long ago to be substantive debates on Supply,
the opportunity for the House to debate and then refuse Supply in one single
division hardly exists; it might be possible on Second Reading of the Finance
and Appropriation Bills, but even that is not certain. A defeat on a specific
Estimate would not in itself constitute a vote of no confidence; Prime Minister
Balfour refused in 1905 to treat such a defeat as a vote of censure. For the
House to demonstrate its lack of confidence in the government by denying it
Supply would necessitate now a series of defeats. Such action would seem
perverse given that the desired outcome could be achieved by one explicit vote
of no confidence. Only in the unlikely (and unprecedented) event of a
government seeking to ignore a defeat on a explicit motion of confidence would
it be likely that the House would resort to denying Supply through a series of
negative votes.
Defeats on Items Central to Government
Policy
If defeated on an item regarded as central
to its policy, but one not made an issue of confidence by prior declaration,
the government may either seek an explicit vote of confidence from the House or
resign or request a dissolution. The effect of deciding on the latter course
(resigning or requesting a dissolution) would be to make the division
retrospectively one of confidence. It was a course followed on occasion in the
nineteenth century but not one which has found favour with governments in the
twentieth. Not surprisingly, not wishing to jeopardise their tenure of office,
Prime Ministers have preferred to ask the House subsequently to declare its
confidence in the government rather than assuming that such confidence has been
denied in the vote in question. In March 1976, for example, the Labour
Government was defeated on its Expenditure White Paper. Though one member of
the Cabinet raised the possibility of seeking a dissolution, the Cabinet opted
instead to seek a vote of confidence from the House. Such a vote was
forthcoming.
A number of divisions in each Parliament and
one or two automatically each session may be deemed to be on items central to
government policy; notably the Second Reading of major Bills promised in the
Government's election manifesto and, sessionally, the Loyal Address and (as
indicated above) the Second Reading of the Finance Bill. Defeat on a Second or
Third Reading per se would not automatically fall within this category. The two
defeats in this century on Second Readings (in 1924 and 1977) and the one on a
Third Reading (also in 1977) were not treated as falling within it, either by
government or opposition. To qualify for inclusion the motion must be
recognized as central to government policy by the government itself or, failing
that, by the Opposition. The number of divisions that qualify, be it relative
to the total number of divisions or in absolute terms, is a small one.
Defeats on Items Not Central to Government
Policy
Divisions which take place on items not at
the heart of government policy are the most numerous in a Parliament. A Second
Reading defeat on an important Bill may fall within the second category of
defeat above; defeat in one or more of the multiple divisions which take place
during Committee and Report stages usually would not. Defeats in this category
do not raise questions beyond the confines of the issue on which they have
taken place. The government's defeat in 1972, for example, on an amendment to
the Local Government Bill on the issue of which local councils should have
the power to incinerate refuse can hardly be said to have raised the question
of confidence. Indeed, it was a defeat little noticed by either MPs themselves
or by the media. In response to such defeats all that the government need do is
decide whether to accept the defeat or to seek its de facto reversal at a later
stage.
Of the government defeats in the division
lobbies in this century, all but a handful have fallen in this category. They
have included (most frequently) defeats on amendments to Bills, including
Finance Bills, as well as on prayers to annul orders, Ways and Means
Resolutions, on motions for Mr. Speaker to leave the Chair, on adjournment
motions, on various procedural motions, and on a number of declaratory motions,
including Supply motions. None has been considered to strike at the heart of
government policy but a number have not been insignificant either in political
or economic terms. They have, for example, included a change in the standard
rate of income tax, a devaluation of the European Green Pound, and the loss
(following defeat on a guillotine motion) of the Labour Government's main
measure of constitutional reform the Scotland and Wales Bill in 1977. In the
majority of cases the government of the day has accepted the defeats. (All
defeats on Finance Bills, for instance, have been accepted). In only a minority
of cases has the government sought to obtain later reversal. Even then it has
not always been successful: the House refused to reverse the defeat imposing
the so-called "40% threshold" requirement in the Scotland Bill in
1978, instead sustaining the provision by a vote of 298 votes to 243.2 On only
one occasion has the government sought to reverse a defeat by making the vote
for reversal one of confidence. That was in 1944 on an amendment to the
Education Bill, when Prime Minister Winston Churchill appears to have
overreacted by demanding an "adequate" majority. It was a move that
attracted adverse publicity and has not been resorted to by any subsequent
government.
Given the nature of most divisions in the
Commons, and the political significance attached to them by the government,
defeats in the division lobbies will normally fail into this category Defeats involving
questions of confidence in the Government are very much the exception, not the
rule. It may be that if government defeats failing within this third category
nevertheless occur persistently, the government may consider its ability to
govern is impaired. But that is a matter for political, rather than
constitutional, judgement. As long as the government retains the confidence of
the House it may, at its discretion, remain in office until the statutory
five-year maximum for the life of the Parliament reached.
Who Decides?
Who determines into which category a defeat
will fall? The determination rests primarily but not exclusively with the
government. It may, though nowadays rarely does, seek an explicit vote of
confidence from the House. It may determine that a motion to be divided upon
involves fundamentally its ability to continue in office or that, for political
reasons, it should constitute a vote of confidence. It may determine that a
defeat on a particular issue, while not having been declared previously to have
been a vote of confidence, nevertheless raises a question of confidence, and
hence allow the division to fall in the second category of defeat identified
above. Or it may decide and usually does that the issue involved is not one
so central to its policy goals that it raises a question of confidence and so
contents itself with deciding whether or not to accept the defeat. Most
defeats, as already noted, are relegated to this third category.
In determining into which category a defeat
falls, a government will be influenced by a number of factors. These will
encompass both the nature of the issue involved and the circumstances in which
the defeat has taken place. Defeat on a minor amendment to a routine
Departmental Bill will be a straightforward candidate for relegation to the
third category of defeat. Defeats which are the product of opposition parties
combining against a minority government, which are the product of some
deliberate Opposition ploy (opposition members leaving the precincts, hiding in
nearby houses and then rushing back when the division bells sound), or which
are the result of confusion or accident (a number of members stuck in a lift,
for example) will affect the government's assessment as to whether defeat on an
important issue under such circumstances raises a question of confidence. In
1964, when it looked as if the Government might be defeated on an amendment to
the Address because thirteen Labour MPs were fog-bound at a Scottish airport,
the Prime Minister made it clear that if the absence of the MPs resulted in
such a defeat it would fall in the second category of defeat rather than being
construed as a defeat on an implicit vote of confidence. Only in the event of a
defeat on an explicitly-worded vote of confidence can it be said that the
circumstances of the defeat are of no consequence: the government is obliged to
resign or request a dissolution.
Two problems may be identified with the
exercise of this power of determining into which category a defeat falls. One
concerns relegating certain defeats to the third category of defeat; the other
concerns elevating them to the first category. It is the latter problem which
has aroused the greater controversy and generated calls for reform.
A government may relegate to the third
category a defeat on an issue which opponents consider to be central to the
government's policy and hence appropriate for inclusion in the second category,
necessitating a vote of confidence. That governments should err on the side of
putting such defeats into the third category is not surprising. Such action
avoids embarrassing publicity and minimises the potential damage to its
reputation. Should the Opposition nonetheless be convinced that the issue
involved raises a question of confidence it has the option of tabling a motion
of no confidence in the government; in effect, to raise to the second category
a defeat which the government prefers to consign to the third. By convention,
the government makes time available to debate an opposition censure motion.
Hence, this particular power of determination is not exclusive to the
government.
What is exclusive to the government, and at
the heart of the controversy surrounding the issue of confidence, is the power
of government to declare any vote to be one of confidence. For the government
to declare the Second Reading of major Bills, at the heart of its parliamentary
programme, to be issues of confidence as Edward Heath did with the European
Communities Bill in 1972 may be considered a legitimate use of the power.
More controversial is the power to declare minor amendments to entail a
question of confidence. The capacity to abuse this power was well illustrated
by Harold Laski. "Under the Balfour administration of 1900 it actually led
to a question of whether pillar boxes should be green being made a matter of
confidence; and the unfortunate critic of the executive (who was actually one
of its supporters) found himself compelled to deny his own colour preferences.
No one is ever so completely right as to deserve the power to attach to itself
the penalties contingently involved in a vote of confidence."3
It is this capacity to declare a vote, any
vote, to be one of confidence that has led to various proposals for reform.
Most have been aimed at removing the power from the hands of government. One
proposal is that the power to determine what constitutes a 'hanging matter', a
confidence vote, should rest with the Speaker.4 Another is for explicit votes
of confidence alone to be construed as confidence motions.5 A third proposal,
politically and constitutionally the most radical, is for fixed term
Parliaments, with no Provision for dissolution except in extraordinary
circumstances. The problem with the first two proposals is that each would
entail giving potentially contentious political powers to individuals who
occupy positions of political neutrality. The Speaker would be placed in an
invidious position if called upon to determine what was or was not a motion of
confidence. The second proposal would likely entail the Sovereign being drawn
into the political fray, given that the monarch alone could deny a Prime
Minister's resignation or request for a dissolution. Inherent in the third
proposal (fixed term Parliaments) is the risk of subjecting the country to a period
of weak or even no government. Its implementation would also be fraught with
difficulty, constituting a dramatic departure from constitutional and political
norms and practice. It would, in any event, constitute the use of a hammer to
crack a nut.
Though the problem identified is a real one,
it is not perhaps as serious as it is made out to be. It is rare for
governments to elevate divisions to motions of confidence. Various constraints
operate to ensure such restricted use. As Churchill discovered in 1944, making
divisions on amendments to Bills votes of confidence attracts ridicule from the
media as well as from political opponents. It may constitute the exercise of a
constitutional power, but it is an exercise that suggests political weakness.
It is used most often to reduce the incidence of cross-voting by dissident
government backbenchers. Its immediate effect is to ensure that the government
wins the vote. Its medium term effect is to generate resentment among those
dissident backbenchers, an effect that most governments would prefer to avoid
especially if morale on the backbenches is not high. Furthermore, it is a power
that cannot be used on a consistent and regular basis without inviting
political opprobrium from press and opponents and even one's own supporters.
Edward Heath could make the Second Reading of the European Communities Bill a
vote of confidence: he could not easily have done so with the subsequent eighty
divisions that took place on the remaining stages of the Bill. Finally, there is
always the danger that the government might actually lose the vote. Even if
declaring a vote to be one of confidence reduces to nil the number of
cross-votes by dissident backbenchers (though even that is not certain), the
government has no control over London traffic, the operation of' elevators, or
fog at airports. Mr. Heath had a majority of eight for the Second Reading of
the European Community Bill. Fifteen of his own backbenchers voted with the
opposition. Had nine government supporters been held up in traffic, not only
would the Bill have been lost but Mr. Heath would have had to make the
unwelcome trip to the Palace. Fear of losing a vote even if made one of
confidence appears to have served as a clear constraints upon the Labour
Government of James Callaghan, not least in relation to its devolution
legislation.
Conclusion
The essential problem concerning confidence
is not the government's power to make a vote one of confidence. Rather, it is a
problem of perception: the perception on the part of Members of Parliament that
each vote is, in effect, implicitly one of confidence. It is not and
realisation of this by members, and indeed by government, can have, and has had
beneficial effects both for backbenchers on both sides and the government.
Recognition by Members that a government is
constitutionally bound to resign or request a dissolution only in the event of
losing a vote of confidence rids them of a significant and largely self-imposed
constraint upon their parliamentary behaviour. Government backbenchers can vote
against their own side on a substantive issue with the intention of defeating
the government, knowing that by so doing they do not necessarily raise any
wider constitutional issues. The backbenchers get their way; the government
remains in office. Recognition of that fact also imparts to government a degree
of stability. It knows its position is secure unless the vote is one of
confidence. It can thus bear the burden of the occasional defeat without
serious questions being raised as to whether or not it retains the confidence
of the House.
However, recognition of what may be termed
the constitutional reality by itself is insufficient to generate a change in
parliamentary 6ehaviour. As noted earlier, the myth that every vote was
implicitly one of confidence served to reinforce, not to cause, party cohesion.
Recognition of the constitutional reality must be conjoined with the political
will to impose a defeat on government. Members may recognize that they can
impose a defeat upon the government without jeopardising its continuation in
office; such a recognition does not imply that they will do so.
The British House of Commons in the 1970s
witnessed both the realisation of the constitutional position of the government
in the event of defeat and the growth of the political will to impose defeats
by government backbenchers. The Heath government of 1970-74 suffered six
defeats in the division lobbies. Defeat was not necessarily planned by
dissident Conservative backbenchers; but that was the effect of their action.
In response to none of the defeats did the government contemplate resigning or
requesting a dissolution. Gradually, Members realised that the constitutional
as well as the political constraints presumed previously to operate upon them
were largely the imaginative constructs of government and the whip; they had no
basis in constitutional practice or political fact. (The whips, as one Member
observed, "were not so much whips as feather dusters"). Increasingly,
Members began to take a degree of voting independence for granted and a number
of independent-minded government backbenchers notably George Cunningham on
the Labour side were prepared to engineer defeats on those issues on which
they disagreed with government. In so doing, they incurred no hideous
retribution; and the government was able to continue in office. This greater
independence on the part of Members was continued in subsequent Parliaments and
also made possible significant structural reform.
Recognition of the constitutional position
of government in the event of defeat has thus been a partial product of, and
has contributed to, the behavioural and attitudinal change of British Members
of Parliament in recent years. Whether a similar recognition can be achieved in
other Commonwealth Parliaments without a concomitant behavioural and
attitudinal change is for others to determine.
Notes
1. These three categories I identified in
some detail in an article in Public Law in 1978 though they were identified in
broad terms as early as 1936 in a speech in the House of Commons by Prime
Minister Stanley Baldwin.
2. House of Commons, Debates 944,
cols. 597602.
3. H. J. Laski, A Grammar of Politics
(1925), p. 349.
4 Ibid.
5. This proposal is advanced, in effect, by
Nevil Johnson in In Search of the Constitution (1978).