PDF
David E. Smith
This article looks at seven
trends in Canadian politics over the last forty years and how these have
affected Parliament and our understanding of the role of Parliament.
Since the 1970s there have been several major changes that shape
our understanding of Canadian politics. The first has to do with Quebec;
whatever one’s view of what has happened in that province since the late 1960s,
no one, I think, would any longer maintain that the Quiet Revolution was
confined to catching-up with the rest of the country. As incomplete,
inconclusive and controversial as it may be, Quebec has forced Canada to seek
to redefine itself: either as two founding peoples or deux nations,
distinct society, even multiculturalism and bilingualism. Compared to the
certainties or, at least, unquestioned assumptions of the early 1960s, we are,
at best and for the time being, a virtual people.
The second change relates to
Canada’s Aboriginal and First Nations peoples. If the earlier
understanding of the place of the Quebecois in Canada has proven to be
misconstrued, the same cannot be said of the Aboriginal and First Nations
peoples. For in the early 1960s, there was no conception that they had
any place at all. Forty years ago they did not exist as a force in
Canadian politics or as a subject of study in political science. Granted
the federal franchise in 1960, the assumption—articulated at the end of the
decade in the Trudeau government’s White Paper—was that Aboriginal peoples
would be assimilated into Canadian society. The pluralism and diversity,
now heralded as cardinal features of Canada’s constitution and to which the
Aboriginal peoples have been major contributors, remained unrecognized.
A third change is in the area
of rights. In 1964, the Diefenbaker Bill of Rights was four years
old and judged a failure by those who looked for an enhanced affirmation of
rights. The judiciary was deemed too passive, too restrained. The
rights revolution, and its principal Canadian manifestation in the form of the Charter
of Rights and Freedoms, had yet to materialize. Necessarily, the
Charter-skeptics, who now regularly attack the judiciary for being too active
and thus constituting a challenge to Parliament, had yet to appear. After
the Bill but before the Charter, language rights—at the national level
in the form of the Official Languages Act (1969) and at the provincial
level, as in Quebec’s language laws—introduced new grounds for political
organization and action, even when that activity was directed toward court
challenges.
The media is a fourth area of
change. The forty years that this lecture discusses were also the years
of the electronic ‘revolution’. Norman Ward wrote an article once about
the founding of the Canadian Press (with government patronage) and CP’s
maintenance of the Commons Press Gallery. Print medium has transformed
itself over the last four decades, in no small part in response to the spread
of television coverage of politics. The press is less centered on the
House and more devoted to investigative reporting. The compression of
time and space, which the electronic media foster, and their success at
instantaneous coverage have contributed to making the print medium more
partisan in a non-party political sense—that is, more critical of government of
whatever partisan complexion. Twenty-four hour news channels, which are
just a decade old, subject politicians and the viewing public to both a
concentration and breadth of coverage once unimaginable. Much more could
be said—about the contrasting roles of public and private broadcasters, the
adaptability of radio and the rigidity of television when it comes to reporting
local news especially in a national context, as for example, in the coverage of
general election returns. If there is a broadening out of politics as a
result of the modern concern for rights, then television is the ideal medium to
‘nationalize’ or ‘internationalize’ that coverage.
Fifth is the concept of
representation which is all the rage today although the themes advanced are
essentially passive: white, male, middle-class legislators do not reflect
the demographic diversity of the electorate; and the partisan composition of
the legislature does not mirror the distribution of partisan sentiment among
the voters. For these reasons, a recent study published by the Law
Commission of Canada asserts that voters have “essentially wasted their votes.”1
This is one source of the lament about the public’s lack of trust in
politicians, the reputed decline in the political system’s legitimacy, and the
heightened calls for accountability on the part of government. For Norman Ward
and a previous generation of scholars, Parliament’s effectiveness lay not in
passive appearance but active result. Parliament did not make policy—that
was the job of government; Parliament’s task was to debate policy, to set out
its strengths and weaknesses for the electorate ultimately to judge at the
polls. Responsible government, that is, the cabinet-in-Parliament was the
actor. To take recent examples: people want government to act on SARS,
Iraq, BSE, softwood lumber and a multitude of other questions. The
traditional view (that of forty years ago) was that the electoral system could
not carry the weight of what people want. At best it could assure fairness of
the process. (It is worth asking whether a government drawn from a
legislature based on proportional representation would have acted faster or
more effectively in the emergencies of the last couple of years). In any
case, according to the traditional view, only government and the people’s
representatives were in a position to meet that challenge.
That understanding of
parliamentary government gives meaning to the belief in what used to be called
“the morality of the ballot box.” Today this belief is under attack
either in the media or, from organizations whose raison d’être is to
challenge the existing operation of parliamentary government in Canada. I
am thinking of Fair Vote Canada, which describes itself as a citizens’ group
advocating electoral reform, and who the day following the Nova Scotia
election last August, which produced a minority Conservative government, said
the results were ‘proof the current system does not work’. The plurality
system, says Fair Vote Canada, “never gives voters true political
representation because a number of votes are considered wasted."2
A sixth change I call the
development of the audit society.3 One of these new organizations is called Democracy Watch.
It is a revealing name, for in its attack on the administration of
government, particularly on lapses in integrity and in its proposals to prevent
their repetition, Democracy Watch signals that Parliamentary government lacks
democracy. And yet its remedies often possess questionable democratic
credentials themselves. Democracy Watch is a firm believer in the
existing Officers of Parliament (the office of Auditor General, for example)
and champions greater surveillance of elected members and especially ministers.
Officers of Parliament are not a new phenomenon; Norman Ward wrote
extensively about two of them, the Auditor General and the Chief Electoral
Officer. The difference between then and now is that where once seen as
servants of Parliament, they are evolving into its masters. This is a claim,
I realize, with potential for controversy. Nonetheless, what is clear is
that the officers are in the process of becoming the integrity branch of
government, what Bruce Ackerman of Yale University has labeled its fourth
branch.4
The seventh and last change
relates to federalism. I place it last not because it is less important
to Canadian politics than the preceding subjects. Clearly the conduct of
federal-provincial relations is crucial to the future prosperity of the
country. I place it last because I do not think it clearly falls into a
discussion of Parliamentary Democracy in Canada today. In itself, that is
a large claim. Still, the architecture of federalism—the diplomacy of
federal-provincial relations, as Richard Simeon christened it in the 1970s—exists
largely outside of the institutions of Canada’s parliamentary democracy (and no
longer, as traditionally was the case, within the political parties).5
Indeed, it is one of the familiar refrains of critics that these
relations should be brought into parliamentary democracy. Here is the
rationale for transforming Canada’s Senate into a domestic equivalent of
Germany’s, upper house (the Bundesrat) or into a Triple E Senate. While I
could discuss this matter at eye-glazing length and intensity, I do not see
changes in federalism as constituting a transformative political influence on
the operation of parliamentary democracy to the same degree as our altered
perceptions of Quebec, First Nations peoples, human rights, the role of the
media, representation or the rise of the audit society.
Challenges to Parliamentary Government
Let me take the first three
subjects—Quebec, First Nations peoples, and rights as a collective or package.
Some of the implications for politics from this constellation of forces
are obvious: identity politics, the growth of courts as a route to resolve
grievances, the decline in voter turnout, the shift in public and media
attention to claims arising from social diversity or pluralism. All of
this, and more, indicate that one main feature of this development is
accelerated mobility in and out of the traditional political arena. How
is government, how are members of Parliament to retain or recapture that set of
interests? Again, how are the conditions of majority rule as once
understood to prevail in such a kaleidoscopic system?
And there is more. Where
once the judiciary was tangential in the study of Canadian politics; this is no
longer true. Even if one does not share the criticism that the courts are
now trespassing on the Commons and usurping Parliament’s prerogative, there is
no question that the judiciary are elaborating and articulating the lineaments
of the Canadian constitution. In the Quebec Secession reference, for
example, the Supreme Court spoke of the internal architecture of the
constitution and enunciated four of its fundamental features: constitutionalism
and the rule of law, federalism, democracy, and the protection of minorities.6
The courts have found inherent Aboriginal rights in regard to fishing and
hunting. Again, regardless of one’s view of the correctness of these
decisions, the challenge to Parliament here and in other judgments rests in the
limitation they place on governmental action and freedom of manoeuver and,
equally important, on the informative function of parliamentary debate for
public education.
Changing conceptions of
representation and the belief that government needs to be checked—partly
because the scrutiny function of debate in the House has lost favour as members
demand a role in policy-making—has fostered an approach to parliamentary
government that can only be described as republican. Preston Manning
advocates transforming Parliament into a ‘political marketplace’ in which
support is mobilized ‘to force [ideas] higher and higher on the political
agenda,’ and where it is ‘necessary to build and maintain coalitions across
regional and party lines.’7 Some might call the premise of this
proposal—that is, party as enemy and the accompanying plea for the liberation
of MPs—naive. Certainly, it constitutes a rejection of party government
and thus parliamentary democracy as it has operated in Canada for more than a
century. Reformers not only want a separation of powers but they think in
separation-of-powers terms. There is the executive (by which they mean
cabinet) and there is the House. The former dominates the latter because
of party discipline. Party discipline suffocates popular opinion as
expressed through the members. By contrast, they say, direct democracy in
the form of initiative and referendum will circumvent concentrated, centralized
power. But, historically, the referendum has been viewed as alien to
parliamentary democracy as well as incompatible with representative government.
Direct democracy is fed by two
beliefs that have recently gained currency. The first has to do with
listening. It is often said that governments and members of Parliament do
not hear what citizens are saying, and that is because the parliamentary
process offers no opportunity to incorporate citizens’ views. The
attraction of the reformers lies exactly in this—that it offers citizens what
critics say is crucially absent in the Canadian model of politics, the promise
of ‘actually exercis[ing] power and pass[ing] judgment, either directly or
through their individual MPs.’8 Listening is linked to
concerns about inclusion, consultation and the interposition of opinion into
policy-making instruments. Here is the justification for belief in direct
democracy and for disdain of representative government as its poor substitute.
Listening can occur outside
the legislature as well, through extra-parliamentary organizations like the
National Citizens’ Coalition. The NCC must be the most successful
extra-parliamentary organization in Canadian history. Aggregating and
articulating public opinion against Parliament, first with regard to MPs’
pensions, and then the election finance law, the G.S.T. Significantly, the NCC
campaigns used the newspapers to communicate their message to the Canadian
reading public and to provide a channel, via prepared statements to be sent to
MPs postage free, to relay that message to Ottawa. Thus the NCC helped
reduce the sense of difference between governors and governed that has been a
feature of parliamentary government for hundreds of years.
The new order of
politics—with its insistent demands for participation—is flawed, for much of
what people dislike about Parliament is endemic to what a modern Parliament
is—party discipline and executive pre-eminence.
The role of media has been
crucial to the success of the NCC and others who speak in what I call Canada’s
second political vocabulary. But the media have been more than
facilitators in this regard. ‘The “reality” they construct for the
public’ is important not only for how citizens view politics—the launching of
the National Post and the confrontational tone it adopted in its
editorials and coverage of the Chrétien Government helped feed the cynicism
citizens increasingly expressed—but also for how parliamentarians view
citizens.9 Abandon fixed ideas of rank and order and replace them
with mechanisms by which ordinary Canadians might overcome everything that
politically hampers them.
If listening is one modern
belief that is transforming parliamentary politics then resistance to
discipline within opposition and government ranks is a second. Here the
emphasis is not on incorporation from below but on autonomy from above.
Consider the series of intra-caucus conflicts of recent months in the
Liberal party. There is nothing in those controversies that speaks to
citizens, or groups of citizens, or other political parties. Nor is there
mention of negotiations or coalition-building. And the reason is that the
discipline ‘question’ is a concern of those within the citadel who speak the
insider’s tongue, the first political vocabulary. Traditionally,
government has viewed the people as a rival and the expression of opinion
outside of political parties as less than legitimate. The public could
not be admitted because they were not accountable. That gap has widened with
the arrival of the Charter of Rights and Freedoms. Whether it need
be this way is open to debate. Paul Martin’s remarks on the ‘democratic
deficit’ suggest that the House must become more like the people—pluralist.10
Whether that is possible in practice or in parliamentary theory is open
to debate. That is what is missing in these controversies.
In my view, the Liberal
dissidents are also theoretically at sea. On what grounds is party
discipline to be impugned; how far is it to be challenged? The House
cannot return to some golden age of independence where members debated issues
and weighed. Did such a time ever exist in Canada’s parliamentary history?
Wherein lies the authority for the actions Liberal dissidents have taken?
It is intriguing to speculate whether the greater importance MPs now
attach to their constituency role and, indeed, the extra work they do to bridge
the distance between member and constituent are factors leading to a greater
sense of independence. In the debate over Canada’s role in military
action against Iraq, it was common to hear: “MPs must be given the chance to
express their constituents’ views on Canadian military participation.”11
But then again, it was not unique to hear another rationale for
dissent: “to send the Prime Minister a very strong message that attacking
Iraq without UN authorization is not an option.” At the end of the
Chrétien era, some Liberal MPs, either as a representative of someone else or
as a representative of no one but themselves, have taken an interest in guided
independence in so far as procedures are concerned. When in February
2003, twenty-two Liberal backbenchers voted against the wishes of the prime
minister and for an amendment to an ethics bill (C-15, the Lobbyist
Registration Bill), one of their number explained the rationale: ‘On some of
these issues, you have to represent both your own view and the view of your
constituents … It’s not a problem. These aren’t questions of confidence
in the government.’ Thus, on several matters in recent months, discontent
with the prime minister’s treatment of the Liberal caucus has led to criticism
but no defection by Liberal MPs.
Long-time, former NDP Member
of Parliament Ian Deans has said each prime minister sets the tone of the
House. He or she sets the standard of behaviour. If the prime
minister does not care about the House, neither will the Prime Minister’s
Office, and that disdain will spread to cabinet ministers and to the members
themselves. But there is a leadership contest underway and cabinet is
experiencing much tension as a consequence. Following the selection of a
new leader, will the unrest among the renegades abate? In all likelihood,
yes, because there is no coherent theory of parliamentary politics or
leadership to sustain it. At best, it is a half-theory:
emancipate rank and file members but pay no attention to the effect change will
have on the conduct of government. This closed circle approach to
parliamentary improvement omits what is essential and, by contrast, what the
Blair Government’s Memorandum on ‘Modernization of the House of Commons’ at
Westminster has remembered: “The objectives of any programme, must be to
enhance [the executive’s] authority to lead national debate on important
political issues and to improve the capacity of the Chamber and its
Committees to scrutinize Government, both in its executive actions and in
its legislation.” Notwithstanding the Manning-Canadian Alliance
interpretation of a separation of institutions in parliamentary government, the
executive and the legislature are one. It is salutary to bear this truth
in mind if the constructive power of reform is to be realized.
Yes, the prime minister has
too much power. Yes, the PMO sometimes treats ministers and caucus
members with disdain. Yes, members have opinions and, in some instances,
specialized knowledge, and yes, the public believes its demands for
participation go unacknowledged. What conclusion is to be drawn from
these affirmations, and how are they to be incorporated into Canada’s system of
responsible, partisan government?
Conclusion
It is not possible to imitate
the American political system in some piecemeal way, if only because it is a ‘system,’
whose institutions and procedures are locked in reciprocating and dependent
relationships; and if only because Americans voice the same concerns about
politics in Washington as Canadian critics raise about the operation of
Parliament.12 Moreover, if Canadians cannot confidently follow Mr.
Manning’s lead and selectively adopt some American political practices to cure
the perceived ills of their own system, they equally cannot substitute
presidential and congressional government for parliamentary government.
For a start, the rigid amending formula found in Canada’s Constitution
Act provides an effective barrier to any significant institutional change.
What Canadians appear to
want is to know that they can participate in, even though at the same time and
contradictorily they are disengaging from the political process.
Pollsters argue that
Canadians, particularly young Canadians, see government as ‘irrelevant.’ My own
observation is that people come to the political process already polarized and
that the young more than the old, see political matters increasingly in terms
of values. This should come as no surprise, for I think a content
analysis of policy debate in Canada would reveal that issues are discussed
largely in such terms as tolerance, compassion, fairness, equity,
justice, respect, and trust. Look at debate that surrounds the Charter,
medicare and Aboriginal rights, for instance. Today Canadians see values
as the modern equivalent of the bands of steel John A. Macdonald used to unite
the country in the nineteenth century. These values, it is said, define
Canada—usually in contradistinction to the United States.
Societal change of this order
is not unique to Canada: it is happening in Britain and Australia, the United
States and probably most free societies. What is unique is how Canada,
with its distinctive system of parliamentary federalism, responds. I say
distinctive because Canada unlike the United States is doubly federal—of
cultures (French and English defined by law, religion and language) and of
provinces. Indeed, one could argue that a new, third federal dimension,
in the form of Aboriginal (and Northern) self-government, is emerging.
The challenge is how the traditional institutions of parliamentary
government can accommodate both jurisdictional and societal diversity.
As regards the first, on
balance cabinet-parliamentary government has proven itself adaptable to meeting
the diversity of Canada’s jurisdictions and sections. At this point, I
expect to hear muttered dissent along the lines of ‘what about Newfoundland,’
‘what about Alberta?’ To which I would respond: ‘what about them?’
If the poorest and the wealthiest provinces are united in unhappiness
with the status quo, what institutional reform will mollify both? Inter-governmental
problems are always with us. I do not wish to sound dismissive, but
tension is a normal (even healthy) ingredient of legislative, democratic and
federal politics.
It is with regard to the
second, societal, diversity where parliamentary government falls short.
No longer is politics played out almost entirely within the forum of
Parliament and the political parties. Race, sex, gender were but blips on
the political screen when I began teaching in the mid-1960s, and they found no
place in the Canadian politics textbooks of the day. Nor did controversies over
reproductive technology or genetically modified crops, which have spawned their
own aggregations of advocates and opponents outside of Parliament. What
these and other subjects share in common is, first, the decisions they require
are irreversible—which is antipathetic to the view that Parliament is a
sovereign body that never alienates its power; and, second, the knowledge
required to reach a decision is specialized, that is to say it is not the kind
of knowledge most members of Parliament usually possess. Thus
Parliament and the public find themselves subject to the authority of experts
in the public service, academia, and corporations
Today all constitutions—be
they republics, monarchies or, as in the case of Canada, a crown republic—are
attributed to the people. It is this dispersion of popular legitimacy
that Parliament has been unable to reconcile with its centripetal authority.
Attempts at modernization, which usually take the form of advocating more
free votes, less party discipline, grander and more powerful committees have
done nothing to counter the phenomenon of the disappearing Canadian voter.
It remains too soon to know but not unreasonable to doubt whether fixed
election dates, as now statutorily required in British Columbia, or the
introduction of proportional representation (if it happens) will be any more
effective at achieving that object. If so, how then can the unity of
parliamentary government coexist with the diversity of Canadian society?
I would like to conclude in
the confident tones of a telemarketer, that I have the answer to this
perplexing problem, and it can be yours for $34.95, with increased voter
turnout as a bonus. Alas I cannot.
I will end with this quintessential
academic thought. Articulate the problem and you will have taken the first step
to a solution of what ails parliamentary government in Canada today. Why
is voter turnout a concern? Would higher turnout give better
representation, or public policies, or self-worth? Perhaps in an era when
people are given many non-electoral opportunities to promote single-issues,
turning their backs on traditional partisan politics is to be expected.
Perhaps the standard set today for parliamentary politics is so conceived
that it is impossible to attain (or to know if it has been attained).
When Bill Cross, a respected Canadian political scientist, talks about
‘the perennial question of how to make the House of Commons more responsive to
the concerns of the voter,’ what does this mean? For more than a century,
the House of Commons has not been able to respond except through the
actions of the government. The perception of Parliamentary failure,
which is the one many academics, journalists, politicians and the public
indiscriminately promote, takes root because the goals these Jerimiahs preach
are unachievable. Responsiveness is another of those value words whose
meaning lies in the mind of the observer. At the risk of sounding like
Parliament’s poster boy, I believe that the critics must re-examine the
expectations they hold for Parliament. These expectations have to be
realistic; more than that, they have to be specific. Not what should but
what can Parliament do? Even when that hurdle is cleared, expect to be
disappointed. Parliament is at best an approximation of the good.
In the National Portrait
Gallery in London is a lithograph of Samuel Beckett (by Tom Phillips). It will
come as no surprise to those familiar with the enigmatic writer’s work
that the artist has chosen to present the viewer with the back of Beckett’s
head, nor that the tones he used were unrelievably sombre. What really
impressed me about that work was the inscription that accompanied it: ‘No
Matter. Try Again/Fail Again. Fail Better.’ When it comes to
Parliament, let me end with an idea that can be encapsulated in an even shorter
form: ‘lower expectations, raise trust.’
Notes
1. Law Commission of Canada, Renewing
Democracy: Debating Electoral Reform (Discussion Paper, Ottawa: Law
Commission of Canada, 2002), p. 16.
2. Globe and Mail, 7 August 2003, p. A4.
3. For a rigorous examination of this topic,
see Michael Power The Audit Society: Rituals of Verification
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997).
4. Bruce Ackerman, ‘The New Separation of
Powers, Harvard Law Review, vol. 113 (January 2000), pp. 633-96.
5. Richard Simeon, Federal-Provincial
Diplomacy: The making of recent policy in Canada (Toronto: University of
Toronto Press, 1972).
6. Reference re Secession of Quebec,
[1998] 2 S.C.R. 217, paras. 50 and 55-82.
7. Preston Manning, “How to Remake the
National Agenda,” National Post, 13 February 2003, p. A10.
8. Jonathan Malloy, “The Responsible
Government Government Approach and Its Effects on Canadian Legislative
Studies,” Canadian Study of Parliament Group, Parliamentary Perspectives,
No. 5 (November 2002), p. 9.
9. The phrase belongs to Bob Franklin,
‘Keeping it “Bright, Light and Trite”: Changing Newspaper Reporting of
Parliament,’ Parliamentary Affairs, vol. 49 (April 1996), p. 303.
10. Paul Martin, ‘The Democratic Deficit,’ Policy
Options, December 2002-January 2003, 11. (Extract from a speech on
parliamentary reform and public ethics delivered at Osgoode Hall, York
University, Toronto, 21 October 2002).
11. For citations to quotations in this and
the following paragraph, and for more on this subject, see David E. Smith, “The
Affair of the Chairs,” Constitutional Forum, 13, no. 2 (2003), pp.
48-49.
12. See John R. Hibbing and Elizabeth
Theiss-Morse, Congress as Public Enemy: Public Attitudes toward
American Political Institutions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1995), p. 97.
|