PDF
Alex Mazer
Bill C-36, Canada’s anti-terrorism bill,
was drafted under extraordinary circumstances, and was the subject of an
extraordinary debate within and without Parliament. This article
describes the legislative process and broader societal debate surrounding Bill
C-36. Furthermore, it argues that three central lessons can be learned
from studying the discussions of the Bill: that the legislative process should
be “internationalized” to correspond with increasingly international law and
policy; that parliamentary committees can and should be empowered to play an
important role in formulating policy; and that emergency legislation poses
grave dangers and should be made as temporary as possible.
Bill C-36, the Anti-Terrorism Act, was the Government’s
legislative response to the terrorist attacks of 11 September 2001, and
Canada’s domestic contribution to an international legal effort to suppress
terrorism. In the aftermath of September 11, the United States, the
United Kingdom, France, Germany, and Australia, inter alia, all passed
bills with purported objectives similar to those of C-36.
Bill C-36 was complex,
cross-jurisdictional, and unprecedented. It received more public
attention than almost any bill in recent memory. It was tabled in the
wake of one of the most calamitous events in North American history. It
was drafted and studied under considerable time constraints and political
pressures. Perhaps most significantly, it proposed changes that touched
on some our deepest societal values and most profound philosophical ideas – individual
human rights, racial and religious inclusion, national security, and liberty of
the person.
The Legislative Process
Bill C-36 was introduced in the House
by Justice Minister Anne McLellan on 15 October 2001. It was the result of
intensified, accelerated work by Department of Justice officials.
Assistant Deputy Minister Richard Mosley, speaking at a University of
Toronto conference on the Bill, described the behind-the-scenes process by
which the legislation came into being. Immediately after 11 September,
Mosley said, the department conducted a review of all Canadian legislation of
relevance to terrorism – an “already formidable body of law,”1 in Mosley’s words. On 18
September, Minister McLellan spoke in the House about moving forward with
amendments to implement the two international conventions on Bombing and the
Suppression of Terrorist Financing, while also making reference to changes to
the Canada Evidence Act and the Official Secrets Act. At
this point, Mosley suggests, the Bill was still in its early stages within the
Department, where drafters were struggling with “conceptual issues” such as how
– or indeed whether – to define terrorism. The Department continued to
debate the question of definition, among other things, up until 13 October, at which
point the Bill had to be printed to table in the House. However, says
Mosley, “we recognized that this was not going to be anywhere near the end of
the debate and that it would then have to be addressed in a broader public
context and also, of course, within Parliament.” In drafting the bill,
the Department was working under significant time constraints. The most
formal – if not the most important – of these was mandated by United Nations
Security Council Resolution 1373 of 28 September 2001. This resolution
lays out what member states must do to prevent terrorism, and binds states to
report back within 90 days of the resolution’s adoption. In other words,
Canada’s anti-terrorism law had to be passed by the end of December 2001.
In consideration of this deadline, the Bill was tabled two weeks before
the planned date of 1 November.
The Bill was brought before the House
of Commons Standing Committee on Justice and Human Rights on 18 October 2001, following
approximately 8 hours of Second Reading debate and a vote expressing support
for the Bill by a margin of 208-8 (with the NDP caucus opposed). The day
before saw the striking of a Senate Special Committee on Bill C-36, where the
Bill would be sent for a rarely employed procedure called pre-study.
Pre-study is intended to allow the Senate an opportunity to scrutinize
the legislation in concert with the House of Commons, effectively both
assisting the House committee in its consideration of amendments and granting
the Senate a head start in its own scrutiny of the bill.
On the afternoon of 18 October, only
hours after Bill C-36 had passed Second Reading in the House of Commons, Anne
McLellan appeared before the House committee to defend the legislation.
Between 18 October and 22 November, the day the committee tabled its
report with amendments, the Justice committee would hear testimony on the Bill
from approximately 80 individuals. The Senate committee, meanwhile, began
to hear witnesses on 17 October 2001 and submitted its pre-study report on 1
November. After receiving the post-amendment Bill from the House, it
resumed hearings on 3 December and issued its second and final report on 10
December. Over the course of its study of the bill, the Senate committee
heard testimony from approximately 60 witnesses. As parliamentary
committees held hearings a larger debate was happening in the public square,
drawing participation from the gamut of social commentators, including
newspaper columnists, social scientists, jurists, NGOs, religious and cultural
organizations, grassroots activists, and many others.
The Bill’s Content
The overall committee process can be
characterized by expressions of support for the principle of the Bill coupled
with the articulation of a panoply of civil libertarian concerns. In
other words, the overriding timbre of witness testimony – echoed, with slight
variations and temporal shifts, in the wider public debate – was this: we need
a counter-terrorism bill, but C-36 goes too far.
First, let us address the Bill’s raison
d’être. Most witnesses described the C-36 as a response to a
terrorist threat, to a new kind of transnational menace; Justice Minister
McLellan, for one, described terrorist as a “special threat to our way of life.”
It is this threat – or, more precisely, the recent evolution of this
threat – that provided the justificatory basis for the Bill.
In his testimony to the Senate
Committee on October 24, 2001, St. Andrews University terrorism expert Paul
Wilkinson described the 11 September attacks as a “terrible watershed” in the
evolution of terrorism – the dawn of an era of “mass terrorism.” First,
the scale of the terrorist threat is now larger and more international in
character. “Terrorism,” said Wilkinson, “is no longer to be adequately
understood as a law-and-order threat…It has become a strategic threat to the
well-being of the international community and to the human rights of large
numbers of people.” Second, the intent underlying the terrorist threat
has changed. No longer, in the minds of terrorists, is the lethality of
terrorist attacks subordinate to the fear they sow in the people who watch; the
“new” terrorist is less interested in instilling emotions of terror in a
society than he is “hell-bent on killing large numbers of people.”
University of Ottawa law professor
Joseph Magnet described three long-term trends in the evolution of modern
terrorism: first, a decreasing number of terrorist incidents; second, an
increasing lethality of each incident; and third, the adoption of a “war
paradigm” by terrorist networks, in place of “coercive diplomacy.” The
crux of the third trend is that, in the new paradigm, terrorists do not make
demands, as they did in the hostage takings and hijackings of the 1980s.
Rather, in Magnet’s words, “modern terrorism is an act that would be a
war crime if war have been declared.”2
Irwin Cotler, McGill professor, and
member of the House Justice Committee, outlined further dimensions of the new
terrorism in a speech at the University of Toronto. Among these are
included: “the increasing incidence of terrorism associated with or driven by
political, ideological, or religious extremism; the growth and threat of
economic and cyber terrorism; the teaching of contempt and demonizing of the
‘other’; a standing incitement against the demonized target; the dangers of
microproliferation; the potential use of weapons of mass destruction; and the
increased vulnerability of open and technologically advanced democratic
societies like Canada to this genre of terror.”3
The majority of committee witnesses
accepted these assessments of the new terrorist threat, and thus accepted the
necessity of some kind of counter-terrorist legislative response. Even
Alan Borovoy, General Counsel for the Canada Civil Liberties Association and
the de-facto dean of Canadian civil libertarians, argued that “no reasonable
person can quarrel with the goal of this bill.”4 The more germane question from the perspective
of witnesses as well as many intervenors in the broader public discussion was
whether the threat of transnational terrorism justified the specific
law-enforcement measures contained in the legislation – or, put differently,
whether the Bill effectively achieved what the Canadian Bar Association termed
the “delicate balance between collective security and individual liberties.”5
Central to the achievement this
“balance” was deemed to be the amendment or removal of several areas of the
Bill that were regarded as offensive to civil liberties. The first pertains to
the Bill’s definition of “terrorist activity,” the predominant concern being
its overbreadth. The definition included acts that are intended “to cause
serious interference with or serious disruption of an essential service,
facility, or system, whether public or private, other than as a result of
lawful advocacy, protest, dissent or stoppage of work….” Critics charged
that this could include acts of civil disobedience, Aboriginal blockades,
boycotts, wildcat strikes, revolutionary actions directed against oppressive
governments, and confrontational protest activities, among others. The
inclusion of the word “lawful” in the definition drew particular criticism for,
the argument goes, just because an activity (a strike, for instance) is illegal
does not mean it is terrorism.
Another concern was that the definition
did not differentiate between actions taken against democracies and actions
taken against dictatorships, thus preventing Canada from supporting foreign
groups who use violence to combat tyrannical regimes. The reasoning here
is that the legitimacy of an activity depends in part on the governing power
against which it is directed. As expressed by Alan Borovoy in an op-ed
submission to the Globe and Mail, “So long as civilians are not the
deliberate targets of such violence, why should not Canadians be allowed to
support it? Force is often the only way people can free themselves of
dictatorial regimes.”6
Several of the Bill’s critics drew parallels with the illegal and often
violent actions used by the African National Congress and other liberation
movements to overcome apartheid in South Africa. They expressed concern
that, in the South African context, a law such as C-36 would have branded
Nelson Mandela and his collaborators as terrorists.
The Bill defines “terrorist activity”
as an act that is committed “in whole or in part for a political, religious, or
ideological purpose, objective, or cause.” This stipulation – that
motivation should be a determining factor in what is to be considered terrorism
– also drew considerable criticism. Terrorism without such motivations
would still be terrorism, critics said. The Canadian Bar Association,
among others, warned that the inclusion of motivational elements in the
definition could result in the deliberate singling out of specific groups.
“Terrorists are the target of the bill,” the Association said, “not
particular religious ideological groups.”7 University of Toronto law professor Kent Roach went
further, projecting that the “criminalization” of political, ideological, or
religious motivations could constitute a violation of the Charter of Rights
and Freedoms.
A second area of civil libertarian
concern related to the Bill’s provisions as regards “preventative arrest” and
“investigative hearings.” Preventive arrest allows for the arrest and
detention for up to 72 hours of individuals suspected to be on the verge of
committing a terrorist activity. The main preoccupation of critics was
that despite assurances by police that such measures would only be employed
under exceptional circumstances, the powers associated with preventative arrest
could be abused by law enforcement officials. It was suggested that the
Bill should therefore include institutional safeguards to check police power
and protect against the misuse of preventative arrest. Investigative
hearings allow judges to compel individuals to appear before courts as material
witnesses and to prosecute them should they refuse to do so. Among the
concerns here was that the allowance of such hearings would compromise the
constitutionally protected “right to silence.” This right, testified the
Criminal Lawyers’ Association, “is the last bastion against an ever more omnipotent
government.”
A third rights-based criticism of the
bill was that it risked compromising both access to information and privacy
rights. This criticism emanated from a section of the bill allowing the
Minister of Justice to issue certificates prohibiting the release of certain
pieces of information in the interests of international relations, national
security, or national defence. Privacy Commissioner George Radwanski
complained that the provision could be used to “nullify the Privacy Act
by ministerial fiat” because the Act would not apply to the information whose
disclosure would be prohibited by the ministerial certificate. In other
words, the Privacy Commissioner would no longer be able to review the
information, effectively removing the mandate of the Commissioner.
Information Commissioner John Reid told the Senate committee that the
Bill would give the minister “an unfettered, unreviewable right to cloak
information in secrecy for indefinite periods of time.” According to
Reid, the bill would remove the Commissioner’s right to examine information so
as to determine whether secrecy is justified. In sum, the Bill did not
provide a mechanism by which either the Privacy Commission or the Information
Commissioner could oversee the issuance of ministerial certificates.
A fourth civil libertarian concern was
that the bill would unfairly target visible minorities, denying them equal
treatment under the law. Some of this concern grew out the proliferation
of discriminatory treatment by law enforcement officials and of acts of racism
and violence directed against visible minorities – particularly Muslims and
people of Arab origin – in the aftermath of the terrorist attacks of 11
September. The danger of discrimination was evoked most emphatically by
the Canadian Arab Federation, who testified that “the Muslim and Arab
communities in Canada view Bill C-36…as a historically unacceptable, racial,
and religious wedge and an excuse to extinguish the civil liberties of all
Canadians.” They went on to say, “We strongly oppose the misuse of race
and religion to hyperventilate an atmosphere of fear, paranoia and mistrust at
the expense of and in the name of the Muslim and Arab communities, with the
effect of general deprivation of all civil liberties.” This basic concern
was also expressed – albeit less forcefully – in the testimony of the National
Association of Women and the Law, as well as by the Muslim Lawyers Association.
A fifth rights-based concern involved
the advocacy of a so-called “sunset clause” for some – if not all – of the
Bill, a clause that would guarantee the law’s expiry after a specified time
period. This was arguably the area of debate that received the most
attention in the media and in the public arena. Proponents of a sunset
clause argued that the three year parliamentary review provided for in the Bill
was inadequate because, as a 19 November Globe and Mail editorial, put
it … “governments are not known for repealing laws they don’t need or shouldn’t
have.” Among other supporters of a sunset clause in the popular press
were the editorial boards of the Montreal Gazette, the National Post,
the Halifax Daily News, and the Calgary Herald,as well as National
Post columnist Andrew Coyne, Edmonton Journal columnist Lorne
Gunter, Globe columnist Hugh Winsor, La Presse columnist Yves
Boisvert and Vancouver Sun columnist Barbara Yaffe. The sunset
provision was also supported by many of the witnesses who testified before
parliamentary committees, including the Canadian Bar Association, who reasoned
that “when governments seek to impose such restraints on fundamental rights and
freedoms, particularly with limited time available for study and debate, those
restraints must be limited in duration.”
There was much vacillation on the part
of the Government over whether or not to include – or, perhaps more precisely,
whether to allow a debate over – a sunset provision. When justice
minister McLellan appeared before the House justice committee, she declared
herself open to the committee’s review of all parts of the bill, also stating
that the committee was welcome to consider a sunset clause. Meanwhile
Prime Minister Chrétien, speaking from Shanghai, said that he would not support
a sunset clause because the threat of terrorism is permanent, not temporary,
and because putting an expiry date on the Bill could interfere with police
investigations. Further, the Globe and Mail reported a week later that
Chrétien, in a caucus meeting, “challenged arguments from Liberal MPs and that
the legislation should be amended to put time limits on some of the more
controversial elements.” In the end, as mentioned earlier, a five-year sunset
clause was included in the Bill, but only for the provisions dealing with
investigative hearings and preventive arrest.
Aside from a somewhat weakened sunset
clause, the government did accept several substantive amendments from the House
committee’s recommendations. First, the definition of terrorist activity
was narrowed to exclude unlawful, as well as lawful “advocacy, protest,
dissent, or stoppage of work.” Second, an element of mens rea, or
guilty intent, was added to the requirements for criminal responsibility for a
terrorist offence. Third, several safeguards were put in place with
regard to the issuance of Attorney General certificates, including the
subjection of such certificates to judicial review. Fourth, a
non-discrimination clause was inserted to clarify that “political, religious,
or ideological” activity would not in itself be considered terrorism and that
minorities would not be targeted for discriminatory treatment.
Reports of the Senate Committee
But if the government was attentive to
some of the House committee’s concerns, the recommendations of the Senate
Special Committee on Bill C-36 fell on deaf ears. On 1 November 2001, the
Senate committee issued its first report. The report, which was adopted
unanimously by the Senate Chamber of 22 November, expressed serious
reservations about the passage of the anti-terror bill in its existing state
and made a series of far-reaching recommendations about how the legislation’s
problems might be tempered. Included in the recommendations were the
provision for a five-year sunset clause on the entire bill, the appointment of
an Officer of Parliament to “monitor the exercise of powers” provided in the
bill and to report annually to both Houses, the strengthening of safeguards on
preventive arrest and ministerial non-disclosure certificates, and the
narrowing of the definition of terrorist activity. Although the report
may have had marginal effects on the eventual decisions of the House committee,
its recommendations were ignored by the government. The committee’s
second report was far more acquiescent. While the first report warned
that “the bill must reflect a careful equilibrium between rights, privileges,
and duties…and the needs of …a state to protect its citizenry,” the second
report tabled on December 10, 2001 noted witnesses’ suggestions that “security
itself is a pre-condition to liberty.” While the first report contained
unanimous recommendations, the second was divided between Liberal majority
observations, which held that “the very nature of [the] terrorist threat
requires that we provide our law enforcement and security agencies with certain
new tools,” and Progressive Conservative Senators’ Observations, which
expressed continued support for the recommendations of the first report and
submitted that “significant amendments must be brought to [the] Bill before we
can be satisfied that the civil liberties of Canadians will be adequately
protected.”
The First Lesson of Bill C-36
Bill C-36 typified international law
and policy. Yet while this fact may have been taken into consideration
during the drafting of the legislation by departmental officials, who
collaborated extensively with their counterparts in other countries, it was not
reflected in the parliamentary aspect of the legislative process. In
fact, of the dozens of witnesses who testified before the House and Senate
committees, only a handful represented organizations with international
mandates – including Rights and Democracy and Amnesty International Canada –
and only one – St. Andrews University counter-terrorism specialist Paul
Wilkinson – came from outside Canada. There was no consultation with
government officials from nations – such as Spain, India, Indonesia, the United
Kingdom or Israel – who had had previous experience in responding to the threat
of terrorism. There was no consultation with “allies” in the anti-terror
“war” who had put or were in the process of putting in place similar domestic
anti-terrorism legislation, despite the frequent – and almost necessarily
speculative – discussion of other nations’ counter-terrorism regimes by
witnesses and committee members. There was no consultation with American
officials or specialists vis-à-vis the mass detention of individuals –
particularly ethnic minorities – in the United States following the 11
September attacks, despite the fact that this was raised by numerous witnesses
and committee members as a potential lesson on what emergency powers to grant
Canadian law enforcement. There was no consultation with representatives
from the UN or any other international body as to whether the Canadian
legislation conformed with the international counter-terrorism law and policy
regime.
The lack of international input into
the committee process restricted the committee’s ability to ground its
discussion of the Bill in the appropriate historical and political contexts, engendering
a deference to spurious historical-political parallels. Because Canada
has never experienced a terrorist attack against its territory, and thus had
never – prior to the passage of Bill C-36 – implemented a dedicated
counter-terrorism law and policy, the degree to which the bill could be placed
in Canadian historical and political context was limited. The result was
the frequent allusion, particularly by the Bill’s critics, to the War
Measures Act as an analogous piece of legislation, particularly as it was
invoked in response to the FLQ kidnappings of 1970. This parallel was
certainly understandable, given that the October Crisis and the ensuing
implementation of the WMA is arguably the closest Canada has come to an
experience with counter-terrorism law and policy. And yet, as Department
of Justice officials and others pointed out at the time, there are too many
points of disanalogy – both in terms of the historical context and in terms of
the legislation itself – to justify to comparison between the WMA and Bill
C-36. Perhaps most significantly, Bill C-36 came to the legislative table
against the backdrop of the Charter of Rights and Freedoms, whereas the
WMA was drafted and implemented in the pre-Charter era. In
addition, the WMA was intended to be invoked temporarily in instances of “war,
invasion, or insurrection,” whereas Bill C-36 was designed to be permanent
legislation.
The committee’s failure to consider
appropriate international historical and political counter-terrorism analogues,
twinned with the dearth of such analogues in Canadian historical and political
context, ultimately engendered an entrapment of the debate over C-36 within the
ideological polarity of individual rights versus national security.
The characterization of the debate in
terms of a rights-security dialectic was not wholly inappropriate.
However, it did have several important limitations. First, it was a
zero-sum analysis, implying that more security necessarily meant fewer
individual liberties, and vice versa, whereas the legislation’s raison
d’être was the protection of innocent civilians against terrorist attacks,
an objective that arguably favoured the safeguarding of fundamental human
rights as opposed to the curtailing of these rights. As international law
professor Errol Mendes put it in his testimony before the House committee,
“fair balancing…is not just security versus human rights, but one set of human
rights against another set.”8 Second, it effectively excluded other conceptual
parameters from the discussion. To give an example, in some instances the
debate could have alternatively been framed as a dialectic between increased
“security” (through, say, the use of racial profiling in order to keep
suspected terrorists from getting into Canada) and equality (the equal
treatment of all people under the law, including non-residents and
non-citizens). Third, it tended to essentialize the participants in the
debate as being pro-civil liberties if they opposed the legislation and having
little regard for civil liberties if they supported it.
More disconcerting about the
rights-security dichotomy, however, was that it tended to be constructed on
purely ideological foundations, with limited grounding in history and little
knowledge of circumstances beyond Canada’s borders. These shaky
foundations were reflected in much of the commentary – both supporting and
dissenting – surrounding the Bill.
Those supporting increases to security
tended to be dismissive of its potential costs, instead underlining – albeit conjecturally
– the costs of not increasing security. According to National Post columnist
Andrew Coyne, “By refusing to part with our freedoms, we are therefore
condemning a certain number of innocent people to death.”9 Yet Coyne provides no
substantiation to justify this ill-conceived calculus, aside from glibly
remarking, “Were we to live in a police state, or even a mildly autocratic one
such as Singapore, there would very probably be fewer murders in Canada.”
Similarly, a series of Post editorials in November declared
confidently that “our social contract must be amended” in response to the
terrorist threat, but also eschewed any sort of historical or international
comparative justification, aside from the asserting that the detention of 1,200
people, post 11 September, in the United States was “not as terrifying” for the
detained “as being killed by terrorists” (as if it were a one-or-the-other
choice for the individuals being detained). “This country is at war,” one
of the editorials went on, “and in war individuals should expect to make
sacrifices.” These types of crude ideological stances do not lend
themselves to thoughtful debate.
On the other side, although there was a
significantly greater tendency to place restrictions on liberty in historical
context, the typical analysis was to emphasize the need to adhere to civil
libertarian principles, while largely avoiding a discussion of the contemporary
international political context in which the Bill was drafted. In its
testimony before the House committee, the Criminal Lawyers’ Association
declared that “freedom is our most precious treasure”10 but did not address the question of
what restrictions to freedom might result in not crafting an
anti-terrorism legislation. Similarly, the British Columbia Civil
Liberties Association stated in its testimony that “the restrictions on basic
rights and freedoms must be no greater than are reasonably necessary to address
the problems at hand.”11 However, instead of establishing its
critique of the Bill on an awareness of the nature of the “problems at hand,”
the Association declared that “the onus is clearly on the government, and in
particular right now on this committee, to demonstrate where existing
institutions of law enforcement are inadequate to protect our rights and
freedoms.” In other words, it should have been incumbent upon the
government and the committee to justify the need for the Bill. One could
argue that it is also incumbent upon the civil libertarian community to “build
in” to their critiques and understanding of the phenomenon of global terrorism.
On the other hand, there is a more salient lesson here. While it is
perhaps true that civil libertarians were limited in their ability to establish
that the new measures were unnecessary, the more disturbing fact is that the
government, through the parliamentary committees and in the broader debate, was
also limited in its ability to demonstrate that the new law was necessary.
A principal reason for this, I believe, was the near-total omission from
the parliamentary legislative process of an international perspective, a
perspective that could have shed light on both the nature of the international
terrorist threat and the justness of various domestic and international
counter-terrorism laws and policies.
When questioned about the usefulness of
inviting international witnesses to committee hearings, parliamentarians gave
mixed responses. Progressive Conservative MP Peter MacKay indicated that it
would have been particularly helpful to hear from officials from the UK or the
Middle East. He said that at the time, he did some reading about the laws
that other countries had passed, but didn’t feel he would have been able to
conduct a thorough comparative analysis.12 Canadian Alliance MP Vic Toews also stated that the inclusion of
an international perspective would have been useful, underlining the special
utility of Paul Wilkinson’s contribution, but conceded that he hadn’t
considered the idea at the time of the hearings.13 NDP MP Bill Blaikie, too, expressed
lukewarm support for the suggestion, but pointed out that the usefulness of
potential witnesses is difficult to ascertain before hearing their testimony.14
Blaikie also indicated that the time constraints imposed upon the
committee process may have impeded the committee’s ability to consult
non-domestic intervenors. House of Commons Justice committee chair Andy
Scott pointed out that, while the committee did not hear from international
witnesses directly, it did receive a “grid” from the Department of Justice that
compared Bill C-36 with the counterterrorism legislation of other nations.15
But even given the time constraints
imposed on the C-36 legislative process, there exists at least one novel
technique by which the committees could have solicited international input
without having to travel or to bring in witnesses from abroad. The
committees could have invited foreign diplomatic representatives to relate the
experience of their home countries in combating terrorism. In its recent pan-Canadian
consultations leading up to the G-8 Summit in Kananaskis, the Standing
Committee on Foreign Affairs and International Trade heard testimony from
representatives of seven African embassies and high commissions on the New
Partnership for African Development, a centrepiece of the 2002 G-8 agenda.
The Second Lesson: The Danger of Low Expectations
While most students of the Canadian
Parliament agree that “Parliament now plays a marginal role in lawmaking,”
there is some disagreement as to what that role should be. This
disagreement finds particular expression in the scholarly debate over whether
House of Commons and Senate committees should serve more as policymaking bodies
or as forums for public discussion. Professor Jonathan Malloy observes
that while the government and most interest groups view the committee process
in terms of its value as a public forum, committee members themselves tend to
concentrate on the act of making policy.16 He goes on to argue that the expectations on the
part of committee members that they should undertake a major policymaking role
are ultimately detrimental and that they must be brought into line with the
structural constraints of the Westminster style system – namely, strong
partisanship and concentration of power in the executive.
The C-36 experience provides some
insight – although it is of limited generalizability – into the proper role of
committees. Notably, it shows that parliamentary committees can play an
important role in the formulation of policy. This is evidenced by the
number of substantive amendments put forward by the House of Commons committee
and ultimately accepted by the government, in spite of both the time
constraints imposed on the committee and the highly complex nature of the
legislation itself. That said, two special conditions dictated the
committee’s ability to play a policymaking role. The first was the
committee’s unique composition. The fact that justice committee members
tend to have a special personal concern for the issues they deal with caused
the government to have a higher degree of respect for the committee’s work.
“Government members are attracted to this type of committee,” said Andy
Scott, “this isn’t the Finance Committee wannabes; they believe in the subject
matter.”17 Also, several of the committee
members had considerable expertise in the criminal law areas touched on by the
Bill: Vic Toews is former Attorney General of Manitoba, Andy Scott is former
Solicitor General of Canada, Peter MacKay is a former Nova Scotia Crown
Prosecutor and Stephen Owen is former Deputy Attorney General of British
Columbia. Perhaps most significantly, Irwin Cotler, an eminent
international human rights lawyer and McGill law professor, was able to augment
the committee’s ability to operate on a sophisticated policymaking level.
According to Globe and Mail columnist Hugh Winsor, Cotler set “a
new benchmark…for how far a Liberal backbencher can go to confront his
government on its highest priority legislation and get away with it.”18
Cotler supported the bill in principle and was able to achieve several of the
amendments he advocated through continual negotiation with the Department of
Justice and the executive.
The second condition emanated from the
circumstances under which the legislation was drafted. In a way, the
committee had been given a kind of legislative double green light, in that both
the Prime Minister and the Department of Justice had declared themselves
amenable to changes in the Bill. According to Andy Scott, these
circumstances precipitated important differences in how the committee would go
about its deliberations. “Normally, one problem with legislation,” said
Scott, “is that someone wrote it. So there is a defensive instinct.
Amendments can be seen as an affront to the drafters. But C-36 was
drafted so quickly that the government took the position: ‘We may not have it
quite right; take a look at it.’ And the Justice Committee was tasked
with cleaning up the bill.”19
If the C-36 experience shows that parliamentary
committees can, under certain conditions, play a significant policy-making
role, it also underlines their extremely important function as forums for
public discussion. For as was indicated at the outset of this study, the
challenge of developing a counter-terrorism law and policy response to the 11
September terrorist attacks engendered a high level debate in the public square
and it was the work of Commons and Senate committees that served as the
linchpin of this debate. The legislation received extensive coverage in
the popular press and the majority of this coverage made reference to committee
proceedings. The University of Toronto even organized a two-day
conference on the Bill, deliberately scheduled in to coincide with the House
committee’s deliberations. On the occasion of the conference constitutional
lawyer Kent Roach praised the level of societal debate the Bill had generated,
declaring, “the best thing that has happened since 9/11 is not C-36; it is the
increasingly robust democratic process that has surrounded the introduction of
the bill. It is the process…that best honours our traditions”.20
While the experience of Bill C-36
demonstrates how committee proceedings can give rise to vigorous debate in the
public square, some of this debate reflected back on Parliament and pondered
the effectiveness and democratic legitimacy of parliamentary institutions.
Interestingly, the conclusions drawn, at least in the popular press, were
highly ambivalent. National Post columnist Andrew Coyne declared on 21
November 2001, after the Justice Committee passed its amendments, “Glory be:
the system works.”21 The Vancouver Sun entitled its 22 November 2001
editorial, “Ottawa did the right thing,” submitting that the government’s
amendments were “a case in point” that “every once in a while, Parliament works
as it should.”22 Meanwhile,
on 28 November, after the government-invoked closure on debate in the House,
Coyne published another column, entitled “The death of Parliament,” in which he
proclaimed that “the Commons has become a formality, an anachronism.” In
a 29 November 2001 column, the Ottawa Citizen’s Susan Delacourt wrote
that while the committee hearings were “rushed but relevant” and the amendment
process was “not perfect” but “substantial,” the decision to invoke closure
revealed, regrettably, that it was “business as usual in Parliament once
again.” As for the Senate, Globe and Mail columnist Edward
Greenspon suggested that it had “made a useful contribution,” and rather than
criticizing the government’s dismissal of the Senate committee’s
recommendations he submitted that it was proof justice minister Anne McLellan
had “earned her political stripes.”23 Meanwhile, An Ottawa
Citizen opinion piece by Trent University professor Andrew Potter stated
that “the Senate is a dusty old rockpile, but it produced a gem during its
remarkable pre-study.”24
Parliamentarians also offered mixed
reviews of the committee process. Justice committee chair Andy Scott
called it “by far my best experience on a parliamentary committee as a
committee member.” Conservative Senator Lowell Murray said that although
the C-36 experience “proved the value of pre-study,” it was yet another example
of the government’s inattentiveness to the Senate. “We produced a good report,”
he said, “it’s too bad the government didn’t listen.” Conservative MP
Peter MacKay was only partially satisfied with the process: “The committee was
successful in producing legislation that the government wanted, but whether it
was successful in striking the right balance between liberty and security
remains to be seen.” However, said MacKay, “the committee did have very
broad representation of stakeholders.” NDP MP Bill Blaikie was also only
partially satisfied: “The Bill was changed, but not as much as we wanted.”
What are we to make of these mixed
reviews of the effectiveness of Parliament? Two general conclusions can
be drawn: one regarding House committees, and one in relation to the Senate.
As regards the House committee process, the C-36 experience casts doubt
on Malloy’s thesis that the “unrealistically” high expectations of committee
members are “ultimately detrimental.” Bill C-36 shows that committees can
play substantial policy-making roles – even on the government’s highest priority
legislation – given the presence of expert committee members and the openness
of government to amendment. One might be tempted to draw the conclusion
that C-36 was the exception and not the rule, and that parliamentarians keen on
making policy should not expect an iteration of C-36-like conditions in normal
committee work. But this conclusion, however pragmatic, is dangerously
acquiescent and is inimical to the advocacy of hopeful reforms to the committee
process. Rather than reinforce Malloy’s call to lower expectations, the
C-36 experience should raise the ante, not only for the high level of public
discussion committees have the potential to facilitate but also for the ability
of committees to do substantive policy work. Rather than discarding the
lessons offered by C-36 because the Bill’s exceptionalisms, committees should
seek to reiterate the two special conditions that enabled the Justice Committee
to play a policy-formulating role: that is, to recruit parliamentarians with
diverse areas of expertise in law and policy, and to encourage openness to
amendment on the part of the government. As a final aside, we should be
careful not to hold up Bill C-36 as an exemplary committee process. For
while the House committee may have done good work under the circumstances, the
lack of international perspective in the committee’s deliberations and the
constricted timeframe for study of the Bill were not favourable to good
lawmaking.
As regards the Senate, the largely
placid reactions of commentators to the government’s inattentiveness to the
Senate’s pre-study report begs the question: why was there such outrage at the
government’s decision to invoke closure in the Commons and so little at its
eschewing of the Senate’s recommendations? The answer may be partly
related to the Senate’s lack of democratic legitimacy. That is, because
Senators are the political appointees of prime ministers, their input – however
germane, however insightful – is widely considered to be irrelevant. The
overarching public sentiment on the Senate’s role in contemplating Bill C-36
seemed to be one of pessimism: that perhaps the Senate committee had produced a
good report, but no one ever expected that the government would act on it.
This pessimism is regrettable: the Senate committee heard many of the
same witnesses and was arguably composed of as many experts as the House
committee, yet produced a significantly different set of recommendations.
Clearly this diversity of opinion has value, and we should not be so
quick to dismiss the Senate’s findings as irrelevant simply because its members
are not democratically elected.
Third Lesson: The Perils of Emergency Legislation
Bill C-36 was legislated under severe
time constraints. The Bill was drafted in mere weeks by the Department of
Justice and was given Royal Assent only two months after being tabled in the
House. It received nine hours of debate over three consecutive days
during Second Reading, 11 hours of debate over three consecutive days during
Report Stage, and two hours of debate during Third Reading. After five
hours of Report Stage debate, the government put forward a motion of time
allocation, curtailing the Report Stage debate to one further sitting day and
the Third Reading debate to one sitting day as well. The motion, according
to Justice Minister Anne McLellan, was put forward after it “became clear to
the government House leader that opposition members would not co-operate in the
expeditious passage” of the Bill. The decision to shut down debate was widely
criticized in the popular press. A National Post editorial
declared that the government’s invocation of time allocation “undermine[d]…its
seriousness of purpose.” Meanwhile Globe and Mail columnist Hugh
Winsor submitted that McLellan’s and House Leader Don Boudria’s justifications
for moving closure were “either misleading or procedurally specious.” Ottawa
Citizen columnist Susan Delacourt called the government’s decision
“galling.”
The committee process was also
significantly accelerated. The House and Senate committees may have heard
from a significant number of witnesses, but their hearings were squeezed into a
very short time period. Committee members interviewed in conjunction with
this study indicated that a Bill of C-36’s complexity would normally have been
allotted more time for consideration by committee. Said Andy Scott: “If
we had done this in less extreme circumstances, we would have taken quite a bit
longer.” As well, several of the witnesses who testified before the
parliamentary committees indicated that they would have liked to have had more
time to execute a thorough study of the Bill and all its ramifications.
Warren Allmand, President of the Montreal human rights organization
Rights and Democracy and former Solicitor General of Canada, stated in his
testimony that it was “impossible to do a proper review of [the] bill in the
short time that you have.”25
Three important questions arise from
this. First, was the government’s decision to so severely constrict
deliberation really necessary? Second, what are the dangers of rushing
legislation in this manner? Third, what can be done to mitigate these
dangers?
On the first question it is clear that
while the government was perhaps justified in accelerating the legislative
process generally, the restrictions it imposed on debate – particularly the
motion for time allocation – were unnecessary. Part of the government’s
rationale for closing down debate was that it was bound by a deadline by which
to comply with UN resolution 1373, drafted on 28 September 2001, which called
on states to submit anti-terror legislation by 27 December 2001. Yet the
Bill received Royal Assent on 18 December, ten days before the deadline,
meaning the government could have conceivably allowed for several more days of
debate. What is more, the UN deadline was flexible to the calendars of
domestic legislatures: Resolution 1373 states, “the Committee acknowledges the
complexity of the legislation and areas of activity covered by resolution 1373,
and notes that national parliamentary procedures will need to be complied
with.”
But even if the government used the UN
deadline as a fig leaf for its desire to pass anti-terror legislation as
quickly as possible, it appears on the surface that the legislative process
surrounding Bill C-36 was less hastened than the lawmaking that brought its
American counterpart into being. The American Civil Liberties Union
described the US process as “an offence to the thoughtful legislative
procedures necessary to protect the Constitution and the Bill of Rights
at a time when the rights of so many Americans are being jeopardized.”26 According to the ACLU, the US
Senate was presented with the legislation “in a take-it-or-leave-it fashion
with little opportunity for input or review.” Further, it indicated that
no conference committee had been struck to reconcile the differences in opinion
on the Bill between the Senate and the House of Representatives. Although it is
beyond the scope of this inquiry, a comparison between the legislative
processes surrounding the Canadian and American counterterrorism bills could be
a useful area of future research.
In response to the second question, the
simple answer is that it depends on the nature of the legislation.
Clearly, rushing legislation is less dangerous if the bill in question is
minor and technical than if it is far-reaching and transformative. From
this point of view, the quick study of Bill C-36 – not only because of its
complexity but also because of its philosophical profundity – posed particular
dangers. In other words, the task of scrutinizing Bill C-36 demanded not
only the understanding of the novel legal mechanisms contained in the
legislation, but also a coming to terms with the difficult philosophical
questions inherent in the Bill – questions about how much we value liberty, how
much we value security, and what each of these concepts means and how they are
related. These are not questions Canadians ask themselves on a regular
basis, so a thoughtful assessment of them demands time for reflection and time
to distance ourselves from the calamitous events that precipitated the
legislation. Certainly some bills such as C-36, by virtue of their
content, require more time or deliberation than others. But the problem
is that the content of the bill is not the only factor in determining how long
a bill will be debated; political priorities also have a role, and sometimes
these priorities serve to invert the notion that profound legislation should be
studied for longer. When this author asked NDP MP Bill Blaikie whether
the process of lawmaking had changed over the past 20 years, he replied, “Not
really. When it’s really important we spend less time on it; when it’s
not important we spend more time on it. The government uses the fact that
legislation is important to shorten the process.” This raises interesting
questions – although they are tangential to the subject matter here – about
whether there is, in fact, any relation between the nature of the content of
legislation and amount of time spent debating it. Again, these questions
are beyond the scope of this paper, but their answers could provide meaningful
insight into the true influence of committees in the Canadian Westminster
system, a system in which, despite several rounds of reforms to the committee
system, the executive continues to have a coercive impact on committee work.
The dangers of rush legislation, then,
are most pronounced when the legislation is far-reaching and transformative –
as Bill C-36 was. And, positing Bill Blaikie’s rule of thumb, we could
also hypothesize that rush legislation becomes more likely in the face of major
political pressures, which certainly loomed large, both domestically and
internationally, in the case of Bill C-36. If we establish that
“emergencies,” broadly defined, can result in the among the most exigent of
political pressures and if we consider that the powers conferred by emergency
laws tend to be far-reaching and transformative in nature, what we are talking
about in the case of Bill C-36 is not the dangers of “rush” legislation per se,
but more precisely the pitfalls of “emergency” legislation. According to
Oren Gross, an Israeli jurist who has written extensively on emergency
lawmaking, these dangers are manifold.27
First, Gross says, governments have a
tendency to over-react in making legislation under emergency circumstances,
under threat, in a climate of fear, panic, hatred, and other intense emotions.
In doing so, they risk engendering a transplanting the terrorism from
“below” into an institutionalized terror from “above,” and by legitimating the
use of power and force as means of resolving disputes, they risk losing the
moral authority that they possess over terrorist organizations. Second,
emergency legislation tends to be extended beyond the timeframe for which it is
originally intended to apply. The State of Israel, for instance, has been
under a continuous declared emergency regime since 1948. The Civil
Authorities (Special Powers) Act (Northern Ireland), which was originally intended
to expire after one year, was subsequently extended to last for five years, and
was finally transformed into permanent legislation. Third, the longer
that emergency legislation lasts, the more likely it is to infiltrate and have
lasting effects on the “normal” legal system. Gross illustrates this
phenomenon through an examination of the recent history of the curtailment of
the right to silence in Northern Ireland and the United Kingdom. Fourth,
emergency legislation normalizes the powers contained in the legislation and
tends to increase the threshold of what is considered sufficient as a response
to future emergencies. Fifth, the structures and institutions put in
place to implement emergency legislation may remain and continue to exert an
effect even after the legislation itself expires. Sixth, emergency
legislation is often justified by means of a discourse of spurious
“bright-line” distinctions (us-them, permanent-temporary) that crumble under
critical examination. Gross goes on to point out other dangers of
emergency legislation, but the fundamental point is this: we should not
under-estimate (although we often do) the fallout from emergency legislation,
for the differences between “emergency” and “normal” legislation are not as
clear as we might think.
This brings us to the third question,
that is: what can be done to mitigate these dangers? Gross calls for
“rational, calm, and reasoned discourse.” Certainly this is a laudable
goal, and one worth highlighting again and again in exigent political climates.
But what happens when very character of the political climate precludes
“rational, calm, and reasoned” debate? What happens when executive-driven
political pressure severely circumscribes a committee’s legislative timetable (a
particular risk in Westminster-style systems such as our own)? The answer
lies first in the recognition by government that a legislative process was
indeed more hastened than would be desired under normal circumstances.
This recognition – the same recognition that was offered by the
Department of Justice to the parliamentary committees studying Bill C-36 – is
also in effect an acknowledgement of the inherent dangers of emergency
lawmaking, and is thus the appropriate philosophical premise – if not
justification – for maximizing the strength of mechanisms for oversight and
review within the legislation. Bill C-36, particularly in its
post-amendment form, contained several such devices, including: annual
parliamentary oversight by House of Commons and Senate committees; annual
reports to Parliament by the federal and provincial attorneys general and
solicitors general; a three-year parliamentary review; oversight by Privacy and
Information commissioners; the subjection to judicial review of ministerial
certificates preventing the disclosure of certain information for purposes of
international relations, national defence, or national security; the subjection
of orders to preventive detention to juridical review within 24 hours and the
requirement that such orders be consented to by the Attorney General; and, of
course, the possibility of challenging the Bill’s constitutionality under the Charter
of Rights and Freedoms.
But are such oversight mechanisms –
however plentiful, however robust – sufficient antidotes for the widespread
dangers of emergency lawmaking? The answer here, I believe, is a firm
“no.” First, as Gross points out, even when limitations on the
application of new powers are built in to emergency legislation, these tend to
wither away over time. Second, although the legislation can be challenged
before the courts on the grounds that it violates the Charter, Charter
jurisprudence is not necessarily immune from the wider impact of the
legislation. That is, the “creeping” effect that emergency legislation can
have on judicial precedents could make courts less likely to rule the
legislation unconstitutional. Third, no amount of after-the-fact
safeguarding can compensate for the limitations inherent in a legislative
process that was constrained and pressure-laden in the first place.
Fourth, although the Bill does provide for review of the legislation by
Parliament after a period of three years, there is no guarantee that this
safeguard will provide the in-depth scrutiny and the prolonged debate that are
needed.
What is required, rather, is a forced
re-drafting and reconsideration of the Bill, with the benefit of hindsight,
under different political and historical circumstances. As the Senate
Special Committee on Bill C-36 stated in its first report, “Now is a time of
heightened anxiety, fear, and confusion and…it is important that departures
from our legal norms be reconsidered at a time that will allow for sober
reflection and a full evaluation of the effect of these new measures.”28
This “sober reflection” could have only
been guaranteed with the provision for a genuine sunset clause. The two
primary arguments against the inclusion of a sunset provision – that the threat
of terrorism was permanent and not temporary, and that the sudden expiry of the
legislation would interfere with on-going police investigations – were highly
problematic. First, even if we agree that global terrorism constitutes a
permanent, immutable threat – which, considering that the lack of adequate
intelligence makes it quite difficult to assess the extend of the current
threat, is a problematic assertion to say the least – the fact that a problem
will persist does not invalidate the re-thinking of our response to that
problem. Just because the difficulties facing First Nations peoples in
Canada are not going to disappear is not a valid argument against repealing the
Indian Act if we feel it is harmful legislation. Second, the worry
that the sunsetting of the legislation would interfere with police
investigations is perhaps a legitimate concern, but it is largely a technical
matter that could be solved through cooperation between government and law
enforcement officials. The introduction of the new police powers and
procedures ushered in with the passage of Bill C-36 surely also posed technical
challenges for the law enforcement community, but these challenges were never
held up as reasons to oppose the legislation. Third, although it was
argued that the Bill could not be sunsetted because some parts of it involved
the domestic implementation of conventions to which Canada is bound by
international law, these sections of the Bill could have been exempted from a
sunset provision.
A sunset clause would give legislative expression
to the civil libertarian principle that freedoms are much more difficult to
gain than to lose, while acknowledging the concern, frequently expressed during
committee hearings, that the burden of proof in establishing that the
legislation is necessary should lie with the government. A sunset
provision would allow the Department of Justice to re-draft the bill in an
atmosphere of calm, and would grant parliamentary committees the time to carry
out an adequate study of the new bill, including the incorporation into
committee hearings of the international dimension of counter-terrorism law and
policy that, as was argued earlier in this study, was absent during the initial
legislative process. An extended time period for study of the Bill would
also allow for committee travel, either internationally, so as to deepen
understanding of the political and historical context in which global terrorism
exists, or within Canada, to hear citizens – particularly visible minorities –
describe the impact of the new counter-terrorism powers on their lives.
It would also help dissolve the polarization of the debate between civil
libertarians, on the one hand, and those attentive to collective security on
the other. With the new law repealed, those concerned with the effect of
counter-terrorism on civil liberties would not be essentialized as antagonists
in the struggle to uproot terrorism, but rather considered as partners in the
deliberative process of crafting counter-terrorism policy that is effective in
achieving its avowed goal, but that is also protective of essential freedoms
and fair to minorities. At the same time, proponents of counter-terrorism
legislation would not be falsely identified as being indifferent to civil
liberties.
A renewed debate would also allow for a
discussion of the broader economic and political circumstances – the so-called
“root causes” – undergirding the rise of global terrorism, a theme that was
almost entirely absent, within the parliamentary process as well as within the
mainstream media, in the debate surrounding Bill C-36. Such a discussion
could pave the way for a more comprehensive, human security-based
counter-terrorism law and policy – one that considers the eradication of global
poverty, the protection of human rights, the upholding of democratic norms (by
Western as well as non-Western states), the curbing of global diseases, and the
adherence to international law to be objectives commensurate with the
elimination of global terrorism.
Most importantly, for a procedural point
of view, a sunset clause would recognize the inherent incongruity of permanent
“emergency” legislation. For one cannot, on the one hand, justify the
rushed passage of a piece of legislation on the basis that it is an emergency
response to extraordinary circumstances, and, on the other hand, justify the
permanence of the same legislation on the grounds it is to be sustained
response to a threat that is now a part of our “ordinary” global reality.
Notes
1. Ronald J. Daniels
et al, eds, The Security of Freedom: Essays on Canada’s Anti-terrorism Bill,
University of Toronto Press, Toronto, 2001, p. 437.
2. House of Commons
Standing Committee on Justice and Human Rights, Evidence, 31 October
2001.
3. Irwin Cotler,
“Thinking Outside the Box: Foundational Principles of a Counter-Terrorism Law
and Policy” in Ronald J. Daniels et al eds., op. cit., p. 114.
4. House of Commons
Standing Committee on Justice and Human Rights, Evidence, 24 October
2001.
5. Ibid., 31
October 2001.
6. Alan Borovoy, “Does
the antiterror bill go too far?” Globe and Mail, 20 November 2001.
7. House of Commons
Standing Committee on Justice and Human Rights, Evidence, 31 October
2001.
8. Ibid., 6
November 2001.
9. Andrew Coyne, “The
Calculus of Liberty”, National Post, 19 November 2001.
10. House of Commons
Standing Committee on Justice and Human Rights, Evidence, 31 October
2001.
11. Ibid., 30
October 2001.
12. Interview with the
author, 18 June 2002.
13. Interview with the
author, 19 June 2002.
14. Interview with the
author, 20 June 2002.
15. Interview with the
author, 10 June 2002.
16. Jonathan Malloy.
“Reconciling expectations and reality in House of Commons committees: The case
of the 1989 GST inquiry”, Canadian Public Administration, Vil. 39 number
3, pp. 314-335).
17. Interview with the
author, 10 June 2002.
18. Hugh Winsor, The
Power Game, The Globe and Mail, 15 November 2001.
19. Interview with the
author, 10 June 2002.
20. Kent Roach, “The
Dangers of a Charter-Proof and Crime-Based Response to Terrorism”, in The Security
of Freedom: Essays on Canada’s Anti-Terrorist Bill op. cit. p. 131.
21. Andrew Coyne, “A
much less dangerous bill”, National Post, 21 November 2001.
22. “Ottawa did the
right thing”, Vancouver Sun, 22 November 2001.
23. Edward Greenspon,
“Stripes for McLellan, a Bronx cheer for senators”, 6 December 2001.
24. Andrew Potter,
“The power of one: An elected Senate could be the answer to the prime
minister’s style of dictatorial democracy”, Ottawa Citizen, 27 November
2001.
25. House of Commons
Standing Committee on Justice and Human Rights, Evidence, 8 November
2001.
26. American Civil
Liberties Union, letter to U.S. Senators (23 October 2001), www.aclu.org.
27. For an thorough
discussion of the risks of emergency legislation, see Oren Gross, 2001, “Cutting
Down Trees: Law-Making Under the Shadow of Great Calamities”, The Security
of Freedom: Essays on Canada’s Anti-Terrorism Bill, op. cit. Pp.
39-61.
28. Senate Special
Committee on Bill C-36, First Report, 1 November 2001.
|